sequent process. Concerning the paradoxes, the very first thing to do is to determine who is the value-giving subject, and what is the purpose it has in mind when engaging in the information process concerned. In these paradoxes, the value giving subject is obviously whoever decides that the statement involved is a lie. Whenever we use the qualification of true or false, the purpose we have is to assess whether a statement purporting to represent some element of our reality does indeed correspond to that element, which obviously cannot be the statement itself. If the statement refers only and entirely to itself, there is no possibility of a difference between the statement and the reality about which it purports to talk. Even a tautology is not in first instance written as a = a, but as a = b. The identity of a and b is not a foregone conclusion, it is the contribution of the tautology.
In both versions of the paradox there is no element of the world outside the statement to which the statement could correspond: the information is about nothing, so there is simply no information process, as shown below.
ad 1, ‘I am lying now’. In that statement, the value giving subject is ‘I’ and the value is ‘lying, i.e. ‘not true’. It says: -a. That is all there is. For ‘now’ is not an object, but only the chronological situation of the process itself. There is no paradox, but only an incomplete, meaningless, sentence referring to nothing outside itself, and thus not amenable to an evaluation as to its truth. The statement ‘I am beautiful’ is of a totally different nature, for the object is the appearance of the ‘surface’-elements of the living being making the statement, while the value-giving entity is a set of the neurons in the brain of that being which are instrumental in making the assessment which gives value to the image of the being. So the word ‘I’ appears in the statement in two guises: as object (its ‘durface) and as value-giving subject (neurons in the brain), it refers to two different parts of the same individual; it illustrates the appropriateness of distinguishing between the notion of I and of individual, person.
ad2, ‘The sentence on page 123 is a lie’. First note that through all paradoxes of this type runs one implicit assumption: ‘if an expression is not true, it must be false’ and vice versa. The notion that it may simply not be intended to convey anything about the real world is not even considered, which is surprising. For a ‘normal’ person confronted with a sentence which sounds a bit odd will ask: ‘do you really want to say something, and if you do, what is it?’ Even in the logic of propositions - which ‘knows’ only two meanings, true and false - there is a third alternative for evaluation, namely whether the sentence is well-formed or not, whether or not it is a sentence, a ‘formula’, of the language concerned. Let us look at the sentence on page 123 (‘This sentence is false’) and attempt to translate it into a sentence of the logic of propositions. ‘Is false’ obviously is the negation.
The negation is only a connective. If the statement is to be a formula of logic, ‘this sentence’ must be a propositional variable, must be whatever the statement is about, say A. The statement then reads (-A). A propositional variable is a reference to an unspecified aspect of reality about which we want to talk in the language of logic. A propositional variable can stand for any word or sentence, say ‘my nephew is a bore’, provided this variable refers to some element of reality. We must now decide on the propositional variable of the paradox. If we chose for A, then it means ‘anything except A’. Using the above example, it means ‘my nephew is not a bore’.