Russell (Edwards and Pap, p 300) holds that the only rationally defensible view is that any preference for a norm must be subjective; he concludes that such a preference then is a matter of taste. As stated, he did not like his own conclusion and ends with the remark: ‘Whatever our definition of the “Good”, and whether we believe it to be subjective or objective, those who do not desire the happiness of mankind will not endeavour to further it, while those who desire it will do what they can to bring it about...’ (Edwards and Pap, p. 302).
I concur with Russell's last remark, but not with his decision to forego the search for a minimum agreement on what is the ‘Good’. The view of man presented in this book may induce hope that those who desire to further the ‘Good’ might form a majority. But the lack of an adequate aggregation and coordination process, coupled with historical prejudices and mythologies, practically guarantees that those of good will work at cross-purposes and pull in different directions. As long as they fail to agree on a common objective and an adequate organisation of social decision-making, their desire can be perverted and abused by individuals and groups who will exploit it for their own purposes.
Philosophers seem caught in a paradox, they see no passage between the Charybdis of moral totalitarianism and the Scylla of positivism or nihilism. As usual, that paradox finds its origin in an imprecise use of language, in this case about functionality and subjectivity, leading to unwarranted connotations and generally accepted but equally unwarranted tenets of philosophy. In chapters 2a.7, p. 44 (functionality) and 4a.3, p. 133 (subjectivity) those errors have been redressed.
If we see man as a social being and accept the functional character of norms, then holding these norms to be subjective does not mean that they are irrational or random. There is an ultimate judge of norms: the success of societies applying them, a success in which its members have a stake. If people have the shared, if subjective, purpose of achieving coexistence and cooperation under the constraint of subjective equality, if morals have an indispensable function in attaining that objective, then there is no paradox. The passage between Charybdis and Scylla becomes clear if not easy.
The inescapable conclusion is that we cannot - by relegating it to God, nature or ‘reality’ or by retreating into moral nihilism, - shirk the task of establishing, justifying, propagating and applying those norms, The job must be done, and the conclusion of the first volume is that philosophers and social scientist have a role to play. One of those who contested my assertion of the subjectivity of the evaluation of norms works at the same university and faculty as prof. Maris, the author of the book I quoted to support that assertion. That illustrates the extent to which philosophers are ignorant of this responsibility, especially its ‘integration’ part.