A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 1. The Necessary Presuppositions of Philosophy
(1969)–H. Dooyeweerd– Auteursrechtelijk beschermd
[pagina 528]
| |||||||
Chapter II
| |||||||
The fundamental significance of the transcendental ground-Idea for all attempts made in Humanistic immanence-philosophy to classify the problems of philosophy.We have seen that both of these basic factors have dominated Humanistic philosophy since the Renaissance. Before the critical | |||||||
[pagina 529]
| |||||||
philosophy of Kant, however, they were not clearly isolated as a regulative principle for the systematic classification of philosophical problems. The Critique of Pure Reason fenced the first main field of philosophic inquiry: the epistemological foundation and limitation of the classic ideal of science (which is directed toward the ‘domination of nature’). The second main field of philosophical investigation is indicated by the Critique of Practical Reason, i.e. the critical foundation of autonomous ethics, according to the Humanistic ideal of personality. In connection with this latter Critique, Kant treats the philosophical problems of jurisprudence (‘Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre’) and of theology. The Critique of Teleological Judgment (Kritik der teleologischen Urteilskraft) investigates the philosophical problems of biology, historyGa naar voetnoot1 and aesthetics and is thought of as a subjective synthesis between the two other critiques. In Fichte we find a re-occurence of this basic division. He classified philosophy into a ‘Wissenschaftslehre’ with a ‘theoretical’ and a ‘practical’ section. Upon this foundation was subsequently constructed the pantheistic metaphysics of absolute Being. In Hegel's dialectical division of philosophy into logic, natural philosophy, and the philosophy of Spirit, it is not difficult to detect the influence of the same Humanistic ground-Idea. As we have seen, pre-Kantian rationalistic Humanistic philosophy was completely under the influence of Descartes' program of a mathesis universalis. In the naturalistic branch (Hobbes) this program could only lead to an encyclopaedical systematizing of the sciences in a successive continuous procession, from the simple to the complex spheres of knowledge. This was done upon the basis of a mathematical logic and a so-called ‘prima philosophia’. The method of thought of mathematical natural science was maintained in every field of philosophical investigation, in accordance with the con- | |||||||
[pagina 530]
| |||||||
tinuity-postulate of the science-ideal. The same can be ascertained again in Comte's positivism. In spite of their maintenance of the primacy of the science-ideal, we saw that, in the dualistic types of pre-Kantian metaphysics, a fundamental metaphysical cleft was made between natural philosophy, on the one hand, and metaphysical psychology and ethics, on the other. Christian Wolff divided philosophy into two main fields: theoretical philosophy or metaphysics (including natural theology, psychology and physics), and practical philosophy. Pre-Kantian empiristic philosophy could also accept a division into theoretical and practical sections. John Locke, for example, considered philosophy (as a scientific system) to possess three main divisions: ‘physica’ or natural philosophy, ‘practica’ whose principal part constitutes ethics, and ‘semiotica’, whose principal element consists of nominalistic logicGa naar voetnoot1. Even in the philosophy of the XXth Century, attempts at a systematic division continue to be made in accordance with the foundational structure of the Humanistic transcendental ground-idea. Thus we find that Cohen, the father of the neo-Kantian Marburg school, divides philosophy into three principal realms: ‘Logic of pure Knowledge’, ‘Ethics of pure Will’ and ‘Aesthetics of pure Feeling’. Obviously this classification receives its orientation from Kant. The neo-Kantian philosophy of values (Rickert) divides the sphere of real nature from the sphere of ideal values. We have seen in part I, that it seeks to effect a subjective synthesis between the two spheres in the intermediary sphere of culture. The system of values which philosophy must give, according to this standpoint, is grounded in the fundamental distinction between theoretical and practical values. It is not difficult to recognize in this distinction the dualism between the science-ideal and the ideal of personality. Theoretical philosophy becomes a transcendental critique of natural science, practical philosophy a ‘Weltanschauungslehre’. | |||||||
[pagina 531]
| |||||||
Windelband's opinion concerning the necessity of dividing philosophy into a theoretical and a practical section.In his Introduction into Philosophy, Windelband divided the philosophical material into theoretical problems (Wissensfragen) and the axiological ones (Wertfragen). In this context he observes: ‘The connection of both moments (i.e. of the theoretical and practical) is characteristic of philosophy to such a degree, that the division of its historical manifestations into different appropriate periods can be gained in the best manner from the change of the relations between these two. We see how with the Greeks that which is called philosophy originates from purely theoretical interest and methodically comes under the influence of the practical need, and we follow the triumph of the latter in the long periods during which philosophy essentially aims at being a doctrine of the redemption of man. With the Renaissance once more there comes to rule a preponderatingly theoretical striving and the Enlightenment again makes the results of the latter subservient to its practical cultural-ends: until in Kant, with impressive clarity, the intimate coherence between both sides of philosophy is realized and made understandable’Ga naar voetnoot1. Windelband summarily tries to justify this ‘foundational’ distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy by conceiving it as founded upon the two sides of human nature, considered here as a ‘thinking’ and ‘volitional-acting’ being. But this explanation is not serious. For the so-called ‘practical’ philosophy is as much theoretical as the ‘theoretical’ one, and thinking can be either a practical or a theoretical act. | |||||||
[pagina 532]
| |||||||
We quoted the preceeding statement of Windelband to demonstrate how completely dominating the division of philosophy into theoretical and practical is thought to be; it is viewed as not being peculiar to the Humanistic, but to the entire western immanence-philosophy. It is, however, the polar tension between the ideal of science and that of personality, in the basic structure of the Humanistic ground-Idea, that gives this division its particular Humanistic sense. | |||||||
The distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy in Greek thought.The distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy was in fact already present in ancient Greek philosophy. It played a fundamental rôle since Aristotle, and in the Middle Ages it was in many respects accepted without further reflection. The reason for its adoption is readily understood, if we examine the Socratic trend in Greek thought. The path of the latter had been paved by the sophists. As we have seen in our transcendental critique, Greek thought was dominated by the religious form-matter motive. And this motive determined the central content of the various forms of its transcendental ground-Idea. In the Ionic natural philosophy the matter-motive of the old religion of life had the primacy up until Anaxagoras. In the transcendental Idea of Origin, the divine ἄϱχή was conceived of as the formless and impersonal stream of life. And in most instances it was identified with what was later called a mobile element (e.g. water, air, or fire). In Anaximander, however, it was simply referred to as the invisible ἄπειϱον (the formless or unlimited). Under the influence of this transcendental Idea of Origin, man and his culture were viewed under the same perspective as the rest of things, arising in a specific form out of the womb of the eternal flowing stream of life. Man and all things are condemned to death and decay because ‘form’ is ungodly and perishable. In opposition to the matter-motive the Eleatic school posited its counter pole, viz. the principle of form. It developed a metaphysical ontology in which the all-inclusive form of being was qualified as the only true, eternal, and unchangeable entity. However, the form-motive is here still orientated to the old | |||||||
[pagina 533]
| |||||||
ouranicGa naar voetnoot1 religion of nature. As a result, this dialectical trend did not lead Greek thought to critical self-reflection concerning the central position of man in the cosmos. This latter did not occur until the form-motive of the culture-religion acquired the primacy in Greek thought. Under its leadership interest was directed to human culture and in particular to the Greek polis as the bearer of the Olympian culture-religion. In Protagoras, the father of Sophistic, this dialectical trend was accompanied by a sceptical criticism of natural philosophy and metaphysical ontology, a criticism which involved the whole of theoretical knowledge. It drew the most extreme conclusions from the matter-motive of the older nature-philosophyGa naar voetnoot2. If everything is in a constant state of flux and change, this is also true of theoretical truth. There is no fixed norm for the latter. Individual man in his constantly changing subjectivity is the measure of all things. This devaluation of theoretical knowledge of nature had its back-ground in the shift of interest to human culture and in particular to the Greek polis as the sphere of human action. In opposition to theoretical philosophy, which is valueless in itself, was posited a practical philosophy, not concerned with truth, but with what is useful and beneficial to man. In particular its task was to furnish practical knowledge necessary for politics. For by means of its paideia, the polis, as the bearer of the culture-religion, gives form to human nature, which in itself does not posses any law or form, because it is entirely subjected to the ever flowing stream of becoming and decay. | |||||||
The sophistic distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy in the light of the Greek motive of form and matter.Thus, for the first time, a fundamental opposition was introduced between theoretical and practical philosophy, and this | |||||||
[pagina 534]
| |||||||
opposition was entirely dominated by the dualistic Greek ground-motive. The question as to whether primacy was to be ascribed to the motive of form or to that of matter was expressly viewed by Socrates in the light of critical self-knowledge. According to the testimony of Plato in the dialogue Phaedrus - which, if not authentic, nevertheless suits the Socratic spirit perfectly - Socrates wished to know, if his ego was related to Typhon, the wild and incalculable God of destructive storms (a genuine mythological symbol of the matter-motive), or whether he was in possession of a simple (Apollinian) nature, to which form, order, and harmony are proper. Just as Protagoras, Socrates ascribed primacy to the form-motive of the culture-religion. His interests also were entirely directed to culture, ethics, and politics. He was solely concerned in human action. But before everything else he wished to regain fixed norms in philosophical theoria as to the good, the true, and the beautiful. These had been undermined by the critique of the sophists, a critique exclusively inspired by the matter-principle and loosened from the principle of form. The criterion of utility, which Protagoras had accepted for practical philosophy, was in the last analysis itself caught in the matter-principle of eternal flux and change. Therefore, Socrates wished to elevate practical philosophy to an epistèmè, a science. The virtues must be comprehended in a concept. Every concept of an ἀϱετή, however, remains enclosed in the theoretical diversity of the normative aspects. It must therefore be concentrically directed toward the divine Idea of the good and the beautiful, as the origin of all form in the cosmos. This orientation of the scientific method in ethics to the divine form-principle gave a teleological direction to practical philosophy. All temporal laws and ordinances and all things in the cosmos must in the last instance aim at expressing the Idea of the good and beautiful, according to which the divine nous formed the cosmos. A concept is valueless, if it does not inform us of the good of the thing being defined. A concept has value in Socrates' practical philosophy only, if it informs us of the ἀϱετή, the use of a thing. This Socratic Idea of aretè implies in the last analysis the teleological relation to the divine Idea of the good and beautiful. Meanwhile, Socrates sharply emphasized the theoretical character of his ‘practical’ philosophy. He did not counte- | |||||||
[pagina 535]
| |||||||
nance the sophistical opposition of theoria and praxisGa naar voetnoot1. The distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy is not again significant until Plato and Aristotle. For even though they took full cognizance of Socrates' contribution to thought, they again became interested in the problems of metaphysics and natural philosophy. Since primacy was now ascribed to the form-motive of the culture-religion, the motive of matter was deprived of all divine attributes and the deity was now conceived of as pure nous (‘pure form’ in Aristotle). The Socratic influence on Greek thought directed the latter toward the self-hood. And as soon as this critical self-reflection appeared in Greek philosophy, the characteristic of man, which distinguishes him from other beings bound to the principle of matter, was now sought in the nous (reason). This nous was conceived of as theoretical thought. Besides ethical and political questions, the theoria was again concerned with ontological problems and with those of nature. Consequently, the need arose to introduce a distinction in human reason itself. Henceforth, the misleading opposition between theoretical and practical reason was introduced. This distinction is really misleading here! For by ‘practical reason’ (phronèsis in Plato, nous praktikos in Aristotle) was not in the least understood pre-theoretical naïve thought, insofar as it is concerned with practice. In principle, both Plato and Aristotle held to the Socratic view that only theoretical insight into the good can protect human action from being dominated by sensory passions and desires, which originate in the ‘matter’ of human nature. From this view-point the distinction between theoretical and practical reason cannot be founded in the subjective act of thought, but exclusively in the Gegenstand of its logical function. The philosophical ethics and political theory of Plato and Aristotle intend to give theoretical insight into objective norms for ethics and politics. It is indifferent to the inner nature of philosophic investigation that it intends to give theoretical information to practical life. For every theoretical investigation can be utilized by the praxis. This even applies to mathematics and physics which do not have any normative aspects as their ‘Gegenstand’. | |||||||
[pagina 536]
| |||||||
The Sophists referred theoretical knowledge to the matter-principle and thus denied any universally valid standard for theoretical truth. Consequently, only on this standpoint could the antithesis between theoretical and practical philosophy have a fundamental significance for the mode of thought as such. Protagoras maintained a pragmatic standpoint with respect to philosophy: Theoria does not have any value in itself. Its value lies solely in the practical aim that it serves, namely, in politics. Naturally, this extreme nominalistic standpoint cannot recognize norms for praxis which are not conventional. Protagoras' sophistic criterion of utility is purely subjective, but not individualistic, as in his epistemology. The nomos, established by the polis, is the common opinion about good and evil, not that of an individual. It has the task to give cultural form to human physis through its paideia. But, as we have seen, the principle of form is subject here to the matter-principle of the eternal flux and change. Protagoras' evolutionary philosophy of culture is a clear proof of this. The nomos is here only a higher phase of development of the lawless physis. Only with this background in mind can a proper understanding be gained of the realistic standpoint of Plato and Aristotle. | |||||||
The axiological turn of this distinction. The primacy of theoretical philosophy versus the primacy of practical philosophy.In addition to distinguishing between them, Greek thought immediately arranges theoretical and practical philosophy in an axiological order. In the realist-idealistic systems of Plato and Aristotle a higher value was ascribed to theoretical philosophy. On the contrary, the naturalist-nominalistic systems which proceeded from the Sophistic standpoint, though they were also influenced by Socrates' Idea of virtue, depreciated pure theoria and ascribed exclusive value to practical philosophy. In the last analysis, this axiological ordering of theoretical and practical philosophy was connected here with the transcendental ground-Idea of Greek philosophy. For, as we have seen, the distinction acquired an entirely different sense in modern Humanistic philosophy. According to Sextus Empiricus (Adv. Math. 7, 16), the first explicit division of philosophy into ethica, physica and logica was made by Plato's pupil Xenocrates who directed the academy after Speusippos. | |||||||
[pagina 537]
| |||||||
In his TopicaGa naar voetnoot1 Aristotle provisionally took over this method of classification. He subsumed all philosophical problems that are related to the universal under λογιϰαί. The specific physical or specific ethical do not receive any attention in this general branch of philosophy. According to this point of view, in addition to including formal logic, λογιϰαί encompasses metaphysics. If we observe the place here accorded to logic in this wide sense, the influence of the metaphysical (speculative) immanence-standpoint is clearly visible. It is evident insofar as it is related to the metaphysical-universal in its supposed elevation above the cosmic diversity. Metaphysical logic is foundational both for natural and ethical philosophy. In a later part of his Topic and in his Metaphysics Aristotle introduced the main division between practical and theoretical philosophy next to which he placed the Poiètikè, a third main division of philosophy. According to this new division, metaphysics, as the science of the first grounds of beingGa naar voetnoot2, became theoretical philosophy ϰαι᾽ ἐξοχήν. Aristotle ascribed to theoretical metaphysics a higher value than to the other branches of philosophical inquiry; he did so, according to the object of knowledgeGa naar voetnoot3. Practical and ‘poetical’ philosophy possess less value; the former is directed toward ethical and political human activity and the latter toward human creation in technique and art. How is this higher appreciation of metaphysical theoria to be understood? Insofar as metaphysics investigates the absolute ‘formal’ ground of being, it is theology (ϑεολογιϰή). Theoretical reason furnishes us with knowledge of the pure nous as divine ‘actus purus’. And the latter, as Archè, is considered to be the final ‘formal’ ground of being of the cosmos, whereas ‘pure matter’ is the original principle of becoming and continuous change. Theoretical metaphysics, therefore, takes axiological precedence of all practical and ‘poetical’ knowledge. Practical philosophy has its foundations in theoretical philosophy in this metaphysical sense. With this is closely connected the distinction made in | |||||||
[pagina 538]
| |||||||
ethics between the ‘dianoetic’ and the ethical virtues. The former point to theoretical and the latter to practical life. The ‘dianoetic’ virtues are the highest, because they are directed toward theoretical knowledge itself. A life devoted only to sensory enjoyment is bestial. An ethical-political life is human, but a life devoted to theory is divine. In it the divine in man, the nous poiètikos (which is planted in him ϑύϱαϑεν, that is to say, from outside) reveals itself in its purest form. It is evident that this whole appreciation of pure theory depends upon the religious primacy of the Greek form-motive. Pure theoria is the only way to a real contact with the divine ‘forma pura’. The transcendental Idea of Origin has two poles: pure Form versus pure matter. This Aristotelian axiological view of theory and practice was accepted by Thomas Aquinas. He also placed the ‘dianoetic’ virtues above the practical and ethical ones. | |||||||
The primacy of practical knowledge in the naturalistic-nominalistic trends of Greek immanence-philosophy.In giving pre-eminence to theoretical philosophy, the metaphysical-idealistic systems of Greek philosophy held to the reality of the ideal forms. In contrast, naturalistic-nominalist Greek philosophy, influenced by the sophistic subjectivism and the Socratic Idea of virtue, ascribed primacy to practical philosophy. Perhaps it is better to say that they rejected all pure ‘theoria’. The Megaric, Cynic, and Cyrenaic schools apparently did not distinguish between theoretical and practical philosophy, nor does one find in them the division of philosophy into physics, ethics, and logic. Nevertheless, they concentrated their entire philosophical interest on ethics, to which logic (dialectic) was made subservient. Epicurus divided philosophy into a canonic (logical), a physical and an ethical section. The philosophy of nature was treated only for the sake of its ethical utility, namely, insofar as it could liberate the soul from the terrors of superstition and could prepare it for the hedonistic enjoyments of cultural life in wise self-restriction. It accomplishes this task by furnishing an insight into the rigid mechanical coherence of the events of nature, considered as an interaction of atoms in the void. In my Reformation and Scholasticism in Philosophy (1949, vol. I) I have shown that this Greek atomism has nothing to do with the | |||||||
[pagina 539]
| |||||||
modern atomistic view of matter, but originated from the Greek form-matter-motive. The systems of the Stoics also followed the traditions of the Academy in dividing philosophy into logic, physics, and ethics. Primacy was, here too, ascribed to practical philosophyGa naar voetnoot1, even though the philosophic physics (which, in a nominalistic strain, had replaced Platonic and Aristotelian metaphysics) occupied the highest position among the theoretical sciences, because as ‘physical theology’ it should lead to knowledge of GodGa naar voetnoot2. The old Stoic view of nature and deity was also completely dominated by the Greek form-matter motive. God is the ever flowing life-stream in its dialectical identity with the form-principle: he is the primal fire and the Logos of nature. It is the task of ethics to teach us how to live according to this Logos. In Stoic ethics the primacy of practical philosophy is clearly revealed, where - in sharp contrast to the Aristotelian view - it teaches, that the highest human task is found in moral action rather than in theoretical contemplation. All virtues are practical and moral in nature; there is no place for pure ‘dianoetic’ ones as in Aristotle. Zeno traced them back to Φϱόνησις. According to Plutarch, Chrysyppus opposed the philosophers who viewed theoretical life as an end in itself. He contended, that such a view was basically a refined hedonism. It was only agreed that in moral life the correct πϱᾶξις, in conformity with reason, rests upon the ϑεωϱία and blends with it. | |||||||
In Greek immanence-philosophy, the necessity of ascribing primacy to the theoretical or to the practical reason is connected with the dialectical form-matter motive.Our discussion should disclose the fact, that the modern Humanistic ideals of science and personality did not play a rôle in the Greek distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy, but that the latter originated from the religious form-matter motive in its dialectical development within philosophic thought. As we saw, this distinction made its entry in Sophistic under the influence of the dialectical opposition of physis and | |||||||
[pagina 540]
| |||||||
nomos, as a dialectical antithesis of pure matter and cultural form (due to the paideia of the polis as the bearer of the cultural religion). It appeared that the further development of the distinction, and the question about the primacy of theoretical or practical philosophy, is closely connected with the dialectical antithesis between the realist-idealistic and the nominalist-naturalistic elaboration of the form-motive, conceived in conformity with the cultural religion. The nous is elevated to the rank of the form-principle of human nature. This nous, as a pseudo-Archimedean point, is imprisoned in the modal diversity of meaning. Realist-idealistic attempts to surmount the modal diversity in a transcendental Idea of the Origin of all forms, theologically leads to an absolutizing of theoretical thought as divine nous, and the latter is then thought of as ‘pure form without matter’. ‘Practical reason’, because bound to the aim of conducting temporal human behaviour, is always related to the matter-principle of human nature. Therefore, it lacks the perfection of pure theoretical thought. The primacy of theoretical reason cannot be maintained unless this hypostatization of theoretical thought is made. Naturalistic nominalism does not join in this metaphysical hypostatization of ‘pure thought’ to ‘pure form’ lifted out of the cosmic coherence of meaning. Yet, if it did not wish to abandon the Socratic trend toward the ethical form of the selfhood, nor to accept the Sophistic nihilism as to theoretical truth, it could only escape the extreme dualism between theoretical and practical reason by axiologically subordinating theoretical philosophy to practical ethics. But the basic antinomy between theoretical and practical reason in Stoic and Epicurean philosophy testifies to the fact that the two poles in the transcendental ground-Idea of Greek thought were no more reconciled in naturalistic nominalism than in idealistic realism. | |||||||
Why we cannot divide philosophy into a theoretical and a practical.Our conclusion is, that the basic division of philosophy into a theoretical and practical section, as well as the division between nature- and spirit-philosophy, are intrinsically connected with the immanence standpoint and its conception of the human selfhood. This division points to an inner dissension in the Archimedean point, a discord, which necessarily leads to the ascription of primacy to theoretical or practical philosophy. | |||||||
[pagina 541]
| |||||||
From the standpoint of re-formed Christian philosophy, in view of its transcendental ground-Idea, this distinction must be discarded in all of its many forms. Our rejection is not made, because we will not have anything to do with immanence philosophy, but because the division in question is incompatible with the Biblical ground-motive of our philosophical thought. We have seen, that the human selfhood as the religious root, as the heart of our entire existence, transcends the temporal limits of our cosmos. It transcends all the modal aspects. Philosophy, directed toward the totality of meaning, in the whole of its activity, is necessarily of a theoretical character. From a Christian point of view, therefore, it is meaningless and even dangerous to take over a basic classification, employed by immanence philosophy, which is rooted in the intrinsic dissension of its Archimedian point. Upon a re-formed Christian standpoint ‘practical reason’ cannot bridge over the fundamental diversity of the normative modal aspects of our cosmos. And neither a theoretical, nor a practical reason, in the sense of immanence philosophy, is identical with our veritable transcendent selfhood. | |||||||
§ 2 - The systematic development of the philosophy of the cosmonomic idea in accordance with indissolubly cohering themataIn the light of our transcendental ground-Idea, philosophical investigation ought to be carried out in accord with the following fundamental, but mutually inseparably cohering themata (themes):
| |||||||
[pagina 542]
| |||||||
The problem of time cannot be a particular theme, since it has a universal transcendental character, and as such embraces every particular philosophical question. It is the transcendental background of all our further inquiries. In this volume, we have concluded the discussion of the first theme, the transcendental criticism of philosophy. We are left with the task of applying this ὑπόϑεσις to the four remaining themata. But the fifth, that of philosophical anthropology, will be treated separately in our new trilogy Reformation and Scholasticism in Philosophy, especially in the third volume. | |||||||
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea does not recognize any dualistic division of philosophy. The themata develop the same philosophical basic problem in moments which are united in the transcendental ground-Idea, in its relation to the different structures of cosmic time. These moments are inseparably linked together.This thematization is not intended to be a division of the philosophical fields of investigation in the sense of a delimitation of self-sufficient spheres of problems. We consider such a division to be in conflict with the essence of philosophical thought, as theoretical thought directed toward the totality of meaning. Our entire work is concerned with the religious self-reflection in philosophical inquiry; we cannot allow any single philosophical problem to be viewed in isolation. The psychologized as well as the so-called Critical epistemology sought to set up the problem of knowledge as an independent isolated basic problem. We cannot accept this absolutization of the epistemological questions, viewed as purely theoretical ones, because a really critical transcendental epistemology depends upon religious self-knowledge and knowledge of God which transcend the theoretical sphere. Epistemology is theory | |||||||
[pagina 543]
| |||||||
directed towards the totality of meaning of human knowledge. It is the theory in which our selfhood, having attained the limits of philosophical thinking, returns into itself and thereby reflects upon the limits and supra-theoretical suppositions of temporal knowledge. Thus viewed, what is all of philosophy other than epistemology? But it is evident, that with such a conception of the problem of knowledge, we might at the same time ask: What is all philosophy other than philosophy of the structures of temporal reality or of time? For in all of its dimensions, philosophical investigation signifies the structural theory of temporal reality, directed toward the totality and Origin of meaning in religious self-reflection. Nay - without religious self-reflection upon the meaning of our temporal cosmos, a veritably critical theory of knowledge would be unattainable for philosophy, because our temporal knowledge, in theory as well as in naïve experience, only has meaning in the whole coherence of meaning of temporal reality. Our further investigations will be carried on in accord with the four remaining themata which we have just enumerated. These themata are to be understood as a methodical explication in different respects of one and the same basic problem. They develop this problem in its relation to the different structures of cosmic time and temporal reality, according to the moments which are contained in our transcendental ground-Idea: the transcendental Ideas of Origin, super-theoretical totality and temporal diversity of meaning in its modal aspects (opposed to each other in the theoretical ‘gegenstand-relation’, but coherent in cosmic time) and in its temporal structures of individuality. Only the transcendental ground-Idea gives an account of the method of thematization of philosophy. | |||||||
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea does not recognize any other theoretical foundation than the transcendental critique of philosophical thought.Immanence-philosophy very often recognizes particular philosophical basic sciences as the self-sufficient foundation of the special branches of science and philosophical inquiry. Our transcendental ground-Idea does not permit us to accept any other theoretical foundation for philosophy than the transcendental critique of philosophical thought as such. We do not acknowledge as a true foundation of philosophy a ‘phenomenology’ as developed | |||||||
[pagina 544]
| |||||||
by Husserl or Scheler, nor a ‘prima philosophia’ as in speculative metaphysics. A ‘logic of philosophy’, as is found in Lask, a critique of knowledge as developed by Hume or Kant, as well as the critical ontology of Nicolai Hartmann or a symbolic logic in the sense of the Vienna school, are also unacceptable to us as the basis for all philosophical investigation, because they lack a really critical foundation. Nor do we agree that a philosophy of values, or a philosophy of mind may furnish an adequate basis for all cultural sciences, whereas an epistemology may be the exclusive foundation of the natural sciences. The very notion that philosophy is founded upon self-sufficient basic sciences is rooted in the immanence standpoint. And this is true whether or not philosophy is taken as a coherent whole, or - in the case of a dualistic main division of its field of investigation - in its separate parts. Immanence-philosophy withdraws philosophical thought from a radical transcendental critique. The transcendental critique of theoretical thought, which we have presented in this volume, is, to be sure, the ultimate theoretical foundation of philosophy. This critique is, however, not to be considered as a self-sufficient philosophical basic science, since it gives a theoretical account of the supra-philosophical ὑπόϑεσις of all philosophical thought. Philosophical thought, in accordance with its immanent limitations, remains enclosed within the temporal diversity of meaning, within which no single specific synthesis can be the common denominator of all the others, or of a complex of other syntheses. The philosophy of mathematics, physics, biology, psychology, logic, history, language, sociology, economy, aesthetics, jurisprudence, ethics, and theology, as ‘philosophia specialis’, fall under the third and fourth theme. That is to say, they belong to the particular theory of modal aspects and to the theory of the structures of individuality, insofar as the latter express themselves within the modal aspects of reality which delimit the specific fields of inquiry of the different branches of science. In the sense just specified, no single ‘philosophia specialis’ can function as a philosophical basic science. The particular philosophical pre-suppositions of a special science exert their apriori influence in the most concrete problems of any particular science. We shall later show this in detail. But the particular philosophy of a special science only exists as philosophy, insofar as it examines this foundation in the light of a total theoreti- | |||||||
[pagina 545]
| |||||||
cal vision of temporal reality. And the latter is ruled by the transcendental ground-Idea and the religious basic motive. A philosophia specialis only exists to set forth the basic problems of the special sciences in the all-sided coherence of meaning of temporal reality and to relate these problems to the super-temporal fulness of meaning and to the archè. An isolated philosophia specialis is a contradiction in terms. | |||||||
§ 3 - A closer examination of the relationship between philosophy and the special sciencesAt this point, however, the question arises once again as to whether or not the special sciences can operate independently of philosophy. Although our transcendental critique of theoretical thought has led to a negative answer, a closer examination is not superfluous. For the prejudice concerning the independence of special science in respect to philosophy seems to be nearly unconquerable. It is argued that the special sciences wrested themselves free from philosophy with great difficulty. The Renaissance and the period following are marked by this struggle. Mathematical physics had to fight in order to free itself from the bonds of the Aristotelian philosophy of nature whose doctrine of substantial forms and especially whose non-mathematical conception of natural events was supposed to impede exact physical investigation. In the XIXth century jurisprudence had to struggle against the rationalistic philosophy of natural law (Wolff c.s.). Even to-day, especially for the students of natural science, the example of ‘Hegelianism’ demonstrates the dangers of a philosophy which tries to meddle in the problems of the special sciences. It may be that our transcendental critique has shown the impossibility of the autonomy of philosophical thought in respect to faith and religion. Its argument, however, that even the special sciences lack in principle this autonomy, because they necessarily are founded upon philosophical pre-suppositions, will meet with much more resistance, especially from the side of the exact sciences. And, at least nowadays, we have no occasion to ascribe this resistance merely to a conceited attitude with respect to philosophical reflection as such. Logic, ethics, and aesthetics are generally considered as being parts of philosophyGa naar voetnoot1. In addition, the concession is made that | |||||||
[pagina 546]
| |||||||
there must be room for a philosophy of the special sciences and for a general epistemology. But according to the generally held opinion, philosophy and science must remain separate, in order to insure the ‘objectivity’ of the latter. When special sciences operate within their own sphere and employ their own scientific methods, they are to be considered as being independent of philosophy. | |||||||
The separation of philosophy and the special sciences from the standpoint of modern Humanism.Nowadays, Humanism generally concedes that the special sciences are autonomous with respect to philosophyGa naar voetnoot1. In the positivistic period of the second half of last century, speculative philosophy was completely discredited. It has been extremely difficult for philosophy to regain general recognition. Therefore, Humanist thought now seeks to guard against its old errors and grants complete autonomy to the special sciences within their own sphereGa naar voetnoot2. Even many adherents of the so-called Critical epistemology have changed their attitude in this respect. | |||||||
[pagina 547]
| |||||||
In his critical period, Kant proclaimed three-dimensional space, as an intuitional form, to be a transcendental condition of geometryGa naar voetnoot1. On this ground, several of his followers (L. Ripke Kühn and others) opposed Einstein's theory of relativity. The Marburg school of neo-Kantians, however, hastened to accommodate the Kantian theory of knowledge to the non-Euclidean geometries (Gausz, Lobatschewsky, Riemann, Bolyai and others). The same can be said about the Kantian apriori conception of causal natural law, which was orientated to the classic physics of Newton, but could not be maintained against the modern quantum-physics. An independent philosophical critique of the method and theoretical constructions of mathematical natural science is, however, impossible when epistemology is exclusively orientated to the ‘Factum’ or (as the Marburg school prefers to say) to the ‘Fieri’ of this science, which must be accepted as it is. The universal validity and autarchy of scientific theory must in this case be accepted apriori, since, in rationalistic immanence-philosophy, natural scientific thought occupies the same position in the sphere of ‘natural reality’, as the divine world-order has in Christian philosophy. Epistemology has simply to follow in the footsteps of the special sciences and is thus safe from being in conflict with scientific progress. Philosophy does not guide or give advice but merely reflects upon the course which the special science has followed. It is consequently assured of the good graces of the latter. And the special sciences need take no cognizance of the way in which philosophy seeks to explain epistemologically the course of scientific investigation. The special sciences think they can remain philosophically and religiously neutral. Which sciences can be more neutral than mathematics and physics? When the other special sciences follow the same method, they will need no more philosophical guidance. Even when the methodological monism of the classical-Humanistic ideal of science is called into question, the neutrality of the special sciences is generally permitted to go unchallenged. In this connection we need only recall the views of Rickert | |||||||
[pagina 548]
| |||||||
and Litt with respect to the relationship between philosophy and the special sciences. Nowadays, such conceptions are so deeply rooted in philosophical and scientific circles that very often any divergent opinion is quickly branded as an unscientific return to an antiquated conception of the task of philosophy. Yet we must not be frightened by an overwhelming ‘communis opinio’. We must not hesitate to criticize the current distinction between philosophical and special scientific thought, when it appears to be incompatible with a really critical standpoint. We are not blind to the danger of apriori speculative metaphysics, if it concerns itself with the specific problems of science. It is not necessary to parade before our eyes this past spectaculum miserabile, because we reject in principle every speculative metaphysics and demand an integral empirical method in philosophic investigations. | |||||||
The intrinsic untenability of a separation between science and philosophy.It is impossible to establish a line of demarcation between philosophy and science in order to emancipate the latter from the former. Science cannot be isolated in such a way as to give it a completely independent sphere of investigation and any attempt to do so cannot withstand a serious critique. It would make sense to speak of the autonomy of the special sciences, if, and only if, a special science could actually investigate a specific aspect of temporal reality without theoretically considering its coherence with the other aspects. No scientific thought, however, is possible in such isolation ‘with closed shutters’. Scientific thought is constantly confronted with the temporal coherence of meaning among the modal aspects of reality, and cannot escape from following a transcendental Idea of this coherence. As we have shown in the Prolegomena, even the special sciences investigating the first two modal aspects of human experience, i.e. the arithmetical and the spatial, cannot avoid making philosophical pre-suppositions in this sense. | |||||||
[pagina 549]
| |||||||
The impossibility of drawing a line of demarcation between philosophical and scientific thought in mathematics, in order to make this special science autonomous with respect to philosophy.Is it possible that modern mathematics would escape from philosophical pre-suppositions with respect to the relationships and coherence of the arithmetic aspect with the spatial, the analytic, the linguistic and sensory ones? Is it permissable to include, with Dedekind, the original spatial continuity- and dimensionality-moments in our concept of number? Is mathematics simply axiomatical symbolic logic whose criterion of truth rests exclusively upon the principium contradictionis and the principium exclusi tertii? Does the ‘transfinite number’ really possess numerical meaning? Is it permitted, in a rationalist way, to reduce the subject-side of the numerical aspect to a function of the principle of progression (which is a numerical law) and can we consequently speak of an actually infinitesimal number? Is it justified to conceive of space as a continuum of points? Is it permitted to designate real numbers as spatial points? Is motion possible in the original (mathematical) sense of the spatial aspect? This whole series of basic philosophical questions strikes the very heart of mathematical thought. No mathematician can remain neutral to them. With or without philosophical reflection on his pre-suppositions he must make a choice. The possibility of effecting a complete separation between philosophy and mathematics is especially problematical with respect to so-called pure (‘non-applied’) mathematics, because it is conceived of as an apriori science and its results cannot be tested by natural-scientific experimentsGa naar voetnoot1. Is it not the very task of the philosophy | |||||||
[pagina 550]
| |||||||
of mathematics to investigate the modal structures of the mathematical aspects on which depend all well-founded judgments in pure mathematics? Is it possible to separate the task of mathematical science from that of the philosophy of mathematics by saying that the latter only seeks to explain the epistemological possibility of apriori mathematical knowledge, whose methods and contents must be accepted without any critique? But, by such an attempt at demarcation, mathematics is made a ‘factum’, a ‘fait accompli’, and the possibility of a real philosophical criticism of the latter is precluded. Such an attitude toward the special sciences may be acceptable in the cadre of a transcendental ground-Idea in which the Humanistic ideal of science has a foundational function, but, in the light of our transcendental critique of theoretical thought, it must be rejected as false and dogmatical. It is true that philosophy can only explain the foundations of mathematics, but this does not warrant the ascription of autonomy to mathematical thought, which reaches its focal point in the technique of reckoning, construction, and deduction. Philosophy cannot attribute this autonomy to it, because the mathematician must necessarily work with subjective philosophical pre-suppositions, whose consequences are evident in mathematical theory itself, as we have explained in the ‘Prolegomena’. | |||||||
The positivistic-nominalistic conception of the merely technical character of constructive scientific concepts and methods.The truce between philosophy and the special sciences formulated in the statement that each is to remain in its own sphere, in the final analysis signifies the sanctioning of the positivistic-nominalistic manner of thinking in the sphere of the special sciences. The theoretical scientist is inclined to maintain that - at least in his constructive work - he operates only with technical concepts and methods which are independent of philosophical and a fortiori of religious pre-suppositions. Thus a mathematician, for example, will say: In our profession, when we employ the concept of the actual continuity of the series of real numbers, we do so without any philosophical prejudice. We utilize such concepts merely, because we find them | |||||||
[pagina 551]
| |||||||
practical and instrumental in the acquisition of satisfactory results. Similarly, a jurist will say: we use the concept ‘corporation’ (Rechtsperson) as a construction of thought under which we include a whole complex of legal phenomena. We do so from a purely technical juridical consideration, because it is useful and ‘denkökonomisch’, that is to say, in conformity with the principle of logical economy. Behind this technical construction we grant philosophy complete freedom to seek a social reality, a collection of individuals, or a super-individual ‘person’. Or if we formally reduce all positive law to the will of the state and declare the law-giver to be juridically omnipotent, then we do so, detached from each standpoint which is dependent upon a philosophy of law; we are equally detached from every political state-absolutism. We employ the concept of the source of law in a purely formal sense and thereby only express the fact that all positive law derives its formal validity from the state. We grant to the philosophy of law the complete freedom to criticize a specific statute as being erroneous and in conflict with justice. It is quite free to oppose a political state-absolutism by insisting upon the freedom of personality. | |||||||
The positivistic view of reality versus the jural facts.In spite of such contentions, however, the truth of the matter is, that behind such would-be technical concepts are hidden very positive philosophical postulates. This is especially the case with the appeal to the principle of ‘logical economy’ in order to defend the use of theoretical fictions which do not correspond to the true situation of things within the modal aspect of reality, that forms the specific field of theoretical research. This appeal is characteristic of a nominalistic-positivism. In the general theory of the modal aspects we shall show in detail, that the principle of logical economy has a logical sense only in indissoluble connection with the principium rationis sufficientis, which implies that we really account for the theoretical states of affairs in a sufficient way. It can never justify theoretical fictions, which are only introduced in order to mask the antinomies caused by a false theoretical conception of empirical reality. The ruling positivistic conception in jurisprudence identifies empirical reality with its physical-psychical aspects, that is to say with an absolutized theoretical abstraction. | |||||||
[pagina 552]
| |||||||
In this naturalist image of empirical reality there is no room for modal aspects of an intrinsically normative character. The juridical aspect completely loses its irreducible modal meaning if - in the line of the modern so-called ‘realistic’ jurisprudence - it is reduced to physical-psychical phenomena. The juridical facts are the juridical aspect of real facts and within this aspect the latter cannot be established without jural norms to which they are subjected. As soon as in theoretical jurisprudence which maintains the normative character of the legal rules, this structural state of affairs is lost sight of and the ‘facts’ within the juridical aspect are conceived of as ‘physical-psychical’ ones, there originate theoretical antinomies which are usually masked by the introduction of ‘theoretical fictions’. And again and again it is the principle of ‘logical economy of thought’ which is called into play to justify these fictions. We shall return to this state of affairs in the second volume when we engage in a detailed investigation of theoretical antinomies. In the present context we want only to stress the fact that behind the so-called ‘non-philosophical’ positivist standpoint in jurisprudence there is hidden a philosophical view of reality, which cannot be neutral in respect to faith and religion. | |||||||
The modal-functional and the typical structures of reality.Under the mask of philosophical and ‘weltanschauliche’ neutrality, the technical pragmatic conception of scientific thought has done a great deal of mischief, especially in the branches of theoretical research which find their ‘Gegenstand’ in modal aspects of temporal reality whose laws are of a normative character. To make this clear I will briefly indicate the difference between the typical concept of a structure of individuality and the modal concept of function, which difference is set forth in detail in the second and third volume. In every modal aspect we can distinguish:
| |||||||
[pagina 553]
| |||||||
Some states of affairs taken from the juridical and physical aspects may suffice for the present to make clear this distinction. As we have observed in the Prolegomena, the structures of individuality embrace all modal aspects without exception and group them together in different typical ways within individual totalities. However, they also express themselves within each of their modal aspects by typicalizing the general modal relations and functions. In the juridical aspect of reality, all phenomena are joined in a jural-functional coherence. Viewed according to the norm-side of this aspect, this means, that constitutional law and civil law, internal ecclesiastical law, internal trade law, internal law of trade-unions and other organizations, international law, etc. do not function apart from each other, but are joined in a horizontal-functional coherence, a coherence guaranteed by the modal structure of the juridical aspect itself. When we view only this universal functional coherence between the various sorts of law, we abstract it from the internal structural differences which the latter display. This general functional view-point is highly abstract; it only teaches us to recognize the modal functions within the juridical aspect apart from the typical structures of individuality which are inherent in reality in its integral character. It is absolutely impossible to approach the internal structural differences between the typical sorts of law, solely with a general juridical concept of function. Therefore, it must be clear that the general modal concept of law can never contain the typical characteristics of state-law. Similarly, the general functional coherence between phenomena within the physical aspect is to be abstractly viewed as indifferent in respect to the internal typical differences displayed by reality within its structures of individuality. To discover the general laws of physical interaction, physics views all physical phenomena under the modal functional denominator of energy. The physical concept of functionGa naar voetnoot1 is a systematic concept ‘par | |||||||
[pagina 554]
| |||||||
excellence’, because it possesses the capacity of grasping the universal horizontal coherence of all possible physical phenomena within this modality. As long as this functional view dominates exclusively, scientific thought does not view the actual things of nature with their internal structures of individuality. A tree, an animal, and so on (as well as an ‘atom’, a ‘molecule’, and a ‘cell’) undoubtedly have physical-chemical functions in their internal structure as a thing of nature; but an exclusively functional view of the physical aspect of reality reveals nothing within the energy-relations of the universum that could eventually delineate itself as the typical structure of an individual totality. Such a functional view only discloses external relations of abstract ‘energy’ or ‘matter’, relations, which exceed any internal structural difference, and which are grasped according to the functional aspect of physical law. This functional view was from the outset evident in the formulation of Newton's law of gravitation, which law is independent of the typical structures of ‘things’, and actually dominates the physical universum. A pencil falling to the ground is subjected to this law just as much as the motions of the planets. But there is no single science, except pure mathematics, which is not confronted with reality in its typical structures of individuality. Chemistry essentially investigates the same modal law-sphere as physics, but it can no longer operate solely with a general concept of function, no more than physics itself, since the discovery of the internal atom-structures. Free fluttering electrons may only display bare functional properties of mass and charge, of motion, attraction, and repulsion, but as soon they function, bound within the structure of an atom or molecule, they display specific properties in which internal structural differences enforce themselves. The distinction between modal-functional and typical structures of reality which we have just shown to be present in the juridical and physical modalities, can also be discovered within all the remaining modal aspects. We shall later demonstrate this in detail. | |||||||
[pagina 555]
| |||||||
The absolutization of the concept of function and the illegitimate introduction of a specific structural concept of individuality as a functional one.What have we seen take place under the influence of the positivistic view of the task of science? In keeping with the postulate of continuity of the Humanistic science-ideal, the concept of function was absolutized in order to eradicate the modal diversity of meaning which exists between the modal aspects. At the same time the attempt was made to erase completely the typical structures of individuality which reality displays within the modalities investigated. But, especially in the so-called ‘pure theory of law’ (reine Rechtslehre) and in ‘pure economics’, there often can be observed a curious confusion of the modal-functional and the typical structural view-points. Often unintentionally, under the guise of a general concept of function, a specific concept of a typical structure of individuality is introduced in order to level all other typical differences of structure within the investigated aspect of reality. Consequently, the supposed merely general modal concept of function is in truth transposed into a typical structural concept. Under the guise of an abstract purely functional view-point the so-called Austrian school in its ‘pure economics’, absolutized free market relations at the expense of the other typical structures of society, which manifest themselves within the economic aspect of reality. In the same way the so-called ‘pure theory of law’, developed by Hans Kelsen and his neo-Kantian school, tried to construe a merely functional-logical coherence between all typical spheres of positive law, either from the hypothesis of the sovereignty of state-law or from the hypothesis of the sovereignty of international law. In the first case, all the other typical juridical spheres were in a pseudo-logical way reduced to state-law, in the second case, to law of a supposed international super-state (civitas maxima). The confusion between modal-functional and typical-structural view-points was completed by the pseudological identification of law and state, or of law and super-state, respectively. But if state and law were identical, it makes no sense to speak of state-law. And if - as Kelsen thinks - from a purely juridical view-point all positive juridical norms are of the same formal nature, and typical material differences should be considered as meta-juridical, then it is contradictory to introduce | |||||||
[pagina 556]
| |||||||
into this modal-functional conception of law the typical characteristics of state-law or super-state-law. Just as all other spheres of human society, the state possesses an internal structure of individuality which functions in all modal aspects of temporal reality. This is precisely the reason why the state cannot be grasped in an abstract concept of function, no more than its typical juridical sphere. The modal concept of function is falisified, if under the guise of a merely functional view of law, the whole problem of the sources of law is orientated toward the state or the international community of states, respectivelyGa naar voetnoot1. Setting aside this aberration, it is advisable to make the following clear: The absolutization in scientific thought of the functionalist view-point is not neutral with respect to philosophy or religion. Rather it must be viewed as the fruit of a nominalist view of science which is grounded in the Humanistic science-ideal, although nowadays this latter has undergone a degeneration in consequence of its purely technical conception, especially in the positivist school of Ernst Mach and the younger logical positivism of the Vienna school. In modern times psychology and the cultural sciences have reacted against the complete domination of this functionalistic science-ideal. In the main this reaction comes from the side of the irrationalistic antipode of this functionalism. | |||||||
The dependence of empirical sciences upon the typical structures of individuality. The revolution of physics in the 20th century.I do not deny that experimental and descriptive sciences are strongly bound to empirical reality in its modal-functional and in its typical structures. In other words I do not deny the fact | |||||||
[pagina 557]
| |||||||
that the insufficiency or incorrectness of rationalistic levelling methods can appear in the course of empirical research by the discovery of stringent facts. In the twentieth century physics, for example, underwent a revolution and had to abandon its classic functionalistic concept of causality, matter, physical space and time. The theory of relativity and the quantum-theory have reduced Newton's physical conception of the world to a mere marginal instance. In keeping with the Humanist ideal of science, the classic mechanical concept of causality aimed at an absolute functionalization of reality in a strictly deterministic sense. This concept of causality could not explain the micro-structure of the physical side of reality, disclosed by continued investigation. Planck's discovery of the quantum-structure of energy and Heisenberg's relations of uncertainty made it no longer possible to reduce the physical processes to a bare continuous causal coherence. On experimental grounds, the quantum theory and the theory of relativity radically broke with Newton's conception of matter as a static substance filling absolute space and subject to completely determined causal processes in ‘absolute time’. The discovery of radio-activity taught the physicist to recognize an autonomous physical change which takes place entirely within the internal structure of the atom, and which cannot be explained in terms of any external functional cause. But the discovery of phenomena which cannot be comprehended in a classical concept of function does not in any way insure that they will be interpreted correctly and in a manner that is philosophically and religiously neutral. On the contrary, it is quite obvious, that the scientific attitude of the leading investigators of nature is profoundly influenced by their theoretical total view of reality. It is evident, for instance, that Mach's and Ostwald's opposition to the acceptance of real atoms and light waves, and their attempt to resolve the physical concept of causality into a purely mathematical concept of function, was dependent upon their positivist sensualistic standpoint in philosophy. B. Bavink pointed out that the modern trend in physics which, following Heisenberg and Jordan, declared itself to be in favour of a fundamental abandonment of the concept of causality in physics, did so on the basis of philosophical considerations which it owed to Mach and AvenariusGa naar voetnoot1. | |||||||
[pagina 558]
| |||||||
The conflict concerning philosophical foundations is not alien to the heart of special sciences. In fact it is the physicist who is in danger of uncritically accepting positivist and nominalist pre-suppositions. By blindly contemplating the ‘technical’ side of his field, he is soon inclined to accept, without even being aware of their philosophical implications, a nominalistic view of physical problems and a merely technical-constructive view of physical methods and concepts. From the standpoint of physics alone, may a physicist accept the thesis that a mathematically formulated theory must be considered as correct, if it explains in the simplest way possible the phenomena known up until the present time by bringing them in a functional coherence? In other words is the principle of logical economy in the positivist and so-called empirio-critical sense, in which it is conceived of by Mach and Avenarius, the only criterion of correctness in physics? Recall the conflict concerning Einstein's theory of relativity which was not only conducted in philosophical circles but also in natural-scientific ones. Recall the controversy between Planck, v. Laue, Lenard and other physicists on the one hand, and Schrödinger, Heisenberg, Jordan on the other, in which the question was discussed as to whether or not the physical concept of causality could in principle still be maintained in the further development of the quantum theory. Was the former situation in classical physics a matter of indifference to the Christian examiner of nature? Was it of no consequence to him, that classical physics adopted an essentially rationalistic view of empirical reality in which the entire individual factual side of the physical aspect was fundamentally reduced to the purely functionalistically conceived of law-side? In other words ought we to accept physical determinism as | |||||||
[pagina 559]
| |||||||
correct with respect to the situation of physics in the 19th century, because it could arrange most of the then known phenomena in a systematic functional coherence? And is it immaterial to the Christian physicist, whether or not physics may be identified with the conventionalist conception that the Vienna school has of it? If it really was indifferent to physics to choose a position in this question, the term ‘science’ might become meaningless. For science pre-supposes a theoretical view of realityGa naar voetnoot1, because it must continually appeal to it. | |||||||
The defense of the autonomy of the special sciences from the so-called critical realistic standpoint.From the standpoint of so-called critical realismGa naar voetnoot2, B. Bavink, the famous German philosopher of nature, has tried to make clear that natural science is autonomous with respect to philosophy: ‘The principal point is not at all with what methods and means of thought we should approach things, but rather what resulted and probably will result further from this approach which for centuries we have executed with the greatest success without any epistemology. The whole question is not at all a question of epistemology, but rather of ontology, that is to say, it does not | |||||||
[pagina 560]
| |||||||
matter how I ought to think the world or can or must think it, but how it really is’Ga naar voetnoot1. This statement seems to be philosophically neutral, but it really depends upon a sharply defined apriori philosophical view of the cosmos. It is only meaningful on the condition of our accepting a constellation of reality in which the physical universum is opposed to human thought as a ‘world in itself’, a constellation in which reality is shut off in its pre-sensory natural aspectsGa naar voetnoot2. There is a connection between this view of the cosmos and Bavink's agreement with the epistemological conception of the merely subjective character of ‘secondary qualities’ (the objective sensory properties of colour, smell, taste, etc.)Ga naar voetnoot3. If it is true, however, that cosmic reality, as a universal and temporal coherence of meaning, does not permit itself to be | |||||||
[pagina 561]
| |||||||
enclosed within its pre-sensory sides, then Bavink's view of reality and his conception of the autonomy of science is false. In other words, if the physical aspect of the cosmos is not separate from the psychical-sensory and logical, and, if subject-object-relations exist in reality, then it is meaningless to speak of a ‘nature in itself’. The physical modality of reality does not permit itself to be comprehended by scientific thought apart from a subjective insight into the mutual relation and coherence of the modalities within the cosmic temporal order. | |||||||
Experiments do not disclose a static reality, given independently of logical thought; rather they point to the solution of questions concerning an aspect of reality which, under the direction of theoretical thought, is involved in a process of enrichment and opening of its meaning.The physical aspect of reality does not represent itself in sensory perception as upon a sensitive plate in a photographical apparatus, nor is it arranged ‘an sich’ according to theoretical categories. But, because of the very intermodal coherence of the aspects, physical phenomena have an objective analogon in the sensory ones; they must be subjectively interpreted in scientific thought and thereby logically opened. In this connection the question as to how the physical aspect ought to be understood in its relation to the other aspects of reality is extremely important. The experimental method is essentially a method of isolation and abstraction. Experiments do no more disclose to us the physical aspect of phenomena as a fixed or static reality in itself, independent of theoretical thought, but rather as an opened aspect of meaning, which, in its cosmic coherence with the logical one, is enriched and unfolded by disclosing its logical anticipations under the direction of scientific thought. For, as we have observed repeatedly, every modal aspect of temporal reality expresses its cosmic coherence with all the others in its modal structure. Experiments are always pointed to the solution of theoretical questions which the scientist himself has raised and formulated. Bavink's opinion that in the course of centuries physics has been able to achieve its greatest results without any aid from epistemology is unworthy of a thinker who is trained in the | |||||||
[pagina 562]
| |||||||
history of science and philosophy. The truth is that modern physics rests upon epistemological pre-suppositions which have had to wage a sharp fight against the formerly ruling Aristotelian conception of natureGa naar voetnoot1, and which only little by little have been generally accepted since the days of Galileo and Newton. Most physicists carry on their investigations without being conscious of their philosophical implications and accept the fundamentals of their science as axioms. This sort of philosophical naïvety is very dangerous for a Christian scientist. For in addition to the gains that it reached in physics, Galileo's and Newton's epistemology implied a purely quantitative and functionalistical view of reality. The latter was not restricted to physics and became the very content of the rationalistic Humanistic science-ideal. Bavink's arguments in defence of the philosophical neutrality of physics, which at first glance seem to be strong, on second thoughts appeared to be not free of pre-suppositions which exceed science. Although he rejects apriori rationalism and the nominalist conventionalism of the Vienna circle, his own opinion concerning the philosophical neutrality of science depends upon a specific philosophical view of reality which to a high degree rests upon an absolutization of the functionalistic view-point of natural scienceGa naar voetnoot2, which has no room for naïve experience. | |||||||
The appeal to reality in scientific investigation is never philosophically and religiously neutral. Historicism in science.The appeal to ‘reality’ in scientific investigation is never free from a philosophical and religious prejudice. Allow me this time to choose the example of the science of history. Ranke said of the latter, that it only has to establish how the events have really happened (‘wie es wirklich gewesen ist’). But in the word ‘wirklich’ (really) there is a snare. For it is impossible for a particular science to grasp an event in its full reality. History, as all other special sciences, can only examine a particular aspect of the latter. Consequently, it groups and arranges historical material in a theoretical modal analysis of temporal reality, | |||||||
[pagina 563]
| |||||||
without which it could not focus its attention upon the historical aspect. In the second volume we shall analyze in detail the modal structure of the latter in order to delimit the true ‘Gegenstand’ of historical investigation. This branch of science pre-supposes a theoretical view of reality which has a philosophical character, since historical investigation can only comprehend the historical aspect in its theoretical coherence with the remaining aspects. Now it is extremely easy for Historicism to gain adherents among historians. Historicism, as we know, is a view of reality which eradicates the boundaries between the modalities and subsumes all other aspects of temporal reality under an historical common denominator. In Part II of this volume we have seen how, since the beginning of the 19th century, Historicism exerted an enormous influence upon the foundation of scientific thought. The Historical school of jurisprudence proclaimed positive law to be an ‘historical phenomenon’. At the same time it had a great influence on the current view of society and on the theory of the state. If the state is viewed historically, then it is especially considered in its modal aspect of power. As we shall show in the second volume of this work, power is the central moment in the modal structure of the historical aspect. Under the influence of Historicism this fact has given rise to the idea that the state, in its total reality, is an organization of power. The empirical reality of the state is, in this way, theoretically identified with its historical aspect. As a matter of fact, the integral typical structure of the state is in this way completely misrepresented. It cannot be enclosed in its historical aspect of power, no more than it can be comprehended as a purely juridical, economical, or psychological phenomenon. Its typical structure embraces all these modal aspects, but cannot be identified with any of them. The attempt to comprehend the state purely in its historical aspect of power, accompanied by a claim to religious and philosophical neutrality, results in a view which offers a false theoretical abstraction instead of the state as it veritably exists. | |||||||
[pagina 564]
| |||||||
The conflict between the functionalistic-mechanistic, the neo-vitalistic and holistic trends in modern biology.Biology also offers many examples of a functionalistic view of reality in which a specific modal aspect is absolutized. The theory of evolution developed a mechanical genetic concept of species that eradicated the internal structural principles of individuality. It was believed, that this did not exceed the limits of biological thought. Modern biology has become the scene of a sharp internal controversy due to the different theoretical views of empirical reality. The holistic school has sought to reconcile the conflict between the mechanists and the neo-vitalists. The former operated with a mechanical concept of function, and attempted to reduce the modal aspect of organic life to the physical-chemical which was conceived of in the obsolete mechanistic sense. The neo-vitalists, following Driesch, have seen that the mechanistic method is insufficient to grasp the material examined by biology. Driesch, however, did not attack the mechanistic conception of matter as a purely physical-chemical constellation which should be enclosed in itself and completely determined by mechanical causality. He only denied that organic life can be reduced to a physical-chemical constellation of matter. He did not see that organic life is nothing but a modal aspect of reality. Consequently, he proclaimed it to be a reality in itself: an immaterial entelechy, a substance which would direct the material process without derogating from the principle of conservation of energy. Thus the attempt was made to correct an absolutized concept of function by means of a concept of substance, understood in a pseudo-Aristotelian sense. But this ‘immaterial substance’ was itself the result of a new absolutization. And the latter was destructive for the theoretical insight into the typical temporal coherence between the biotical and the physical-chemical aspects, within the total structure of individuality of a living organism. Holism made the attempt to conquer the antinomical dualism of Driesch's conception. It had the intention to bridge this dualism by a conception of structural totality. The typical structures of individual totalities, however, cannot be grasped in theoretical thought without a correct theoretical insight into the mutual relations between its different modal aspects. The holistic school lacked this insight. Consequently it fell back upon the | |||||||
[pagina 565]
| |||||||
functionalist attempt to construe a conception of the whole of a living organism by levelling the modal boundaries of meaning of its different aspects. Whereas mechanism tried to reduce the biotical aspect to the physical-chemical one, holism followed the reverse procedure. The philosophical conflict concerning the foundations of biology intervenes in the centre of scientific problemsGa naar voetnoot1, and up to now, it is exclusively conducted within the cadre of a Humanist view of science. Can the Christian biologist choose sides in the sense of a mechanistic, a vitalistic or an holistic view of the living organism? Or will he consider it safer to hide behind the positivist mask of neutrality? For it is a naïveGa naar voetnoot2 positivism that has caused the idea of philosophical neutrality to dominate the special sciences. Our conclusion is, however, that the positivistic conception of special science cannot be reconciled to a Christian cosmonomic Idea. As soon as a special science was born, it was confronted with philosophical problems concerning the modal structure of the special aspect which has to delimit its field of research. It makes no sense to say that special science can neglect these problems, because it has to do with the investigation of empirical phenomena alone. Empirical phenomena have as many modal aspects as human experience has. Consequently it cannot be the phenomena themselves which constitute the special scientific fields of research. It is only the theoretical gegenstand-relation between the logical aspect of our thought and the non-logical aspects of experience which gives rise to the fundamental division of these fields and to the philosophical problems implied in it. No more can philosophy neglect the results of special scientific research of the empirical phenomena, because exactly in these phenomena the inter-modal coherence between the modal structures of the aspects is realized. And the typical structures of individuality can be studied only in their empirical realization, on condition that their modal aspects are correctly distinguished. Therefore an interpenetration of philosophy and special science is unescapable, although the former cannot restrict itself to the | |||||||
[pagina 566]
| |||||||
philosophical problems implied in the special sciences, since it has also to give an account of the data of naïve experience.
The relationship between special science and Christian philosophy has up until now only been provisionally considered. It has been treated here within the general cadre of our transcendental critique of scientific thought. What I am suggesting concerning the mutual penetration of Christian philosophy and science, can only be presented in a more concrete fashion after the development of our general theory of the modal aspects and of the typical structures of individuality. With respect to jurisprudence and sociology I have done this in detail in my Encyclopaedia of Jurisprudence (3 vols.), which will soon be published. With respect to the biological problems I may refer to the second volume of my Reformation and Scholasticism in Philosophy. Furthermore, I may refer to many special investigations by others who adhere to this philosophy. For the present our only concern was to show that, in the light of the Biblical ground-motive of the Christian religion, the modern Humanistic division between science and philosophy cannot be maintained. In fact, even upon the Humanistic standpoint this division cannot hold its own against a serious immanent critique. |
|