A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 1. The Necessary Presuppositions of Philosophy
(1969)–H. Dooyeweerd– Auteursrechtelijk beschermdH. Dooyeweerd, A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 1. The Necessary Presuppositions of Philosophy (vert. William S. Young en David H. Freeman). The Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Company, z.p. 1969 (2de druk)
DBNL-TEI 1
Wijze van coderen: standaard
-
gebruikt exemplaar
eigen exemplaar dbnl
algemene opmerkingen
Dit bestand biedt, behoudens een aantal hierna te noemen ingrepen, een diplomatische weergave van de tweede druk van A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 1. The Necessary Presuppositions of Philosophy. van H. Dooyeweerd, in een vertaling van William S. Young en David H. Freeman uit 1969. De eerste druk van deze vertaling dateert uit 1953. Het oorspronkelijke werk verscheen in 1935-1936 onder de titel De wijsbegeerte der wetsidee.
redactionele ingrepen
p. 278: voetnoot ‘1’ heeft in de lopende tekst geen nootverwijzing. In deze digitale editie is de noot onderaan de pagina geplaatst.
p. 401: voetnoot ‘1’ heeft in de lopende tekst geen nootverwijzing. In deze digitale editie is de noot onderaan de pagina geplaatst.
Bij de omzetting van de gebruikte bron naar deze publicatie in de dbnl is een aantal delen van de tekst niet overgenomen. Hieronder volgen de tekstgedeelten die wel in het origineel voorkomen maar hier uit de lopende tekst zijn weggelaten. Ook de blanco pagina's (p. II, XL, 2, 166, 168, 496, 498) zijn niet opgenomen in de lopende tekst.
[pagina I]
A NEW CRITIQUE OF THEORETICAL THOUGHT
[pagina III]
A NEW CRITIQUE OF THEORETICAL THOUGHT
BY
HERMAN DOOYEWEERD Dr jur.
Professor of Philosophy of Law, Free University of Amsterdam Fellow of the Royal Dutch Academy of Sciences
TRANSLATED BY
DAVID H. FREEMAN
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Wilson College
AND
WILLIAM S. YOUNG
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Butler University
VOLUME I
THE NECESSARY PRESUPPOSITIONS OF PHILOSOPHY
THE PRESBYTERIAN AND REFORMED PUBLISHING COMPANY
1969
[pagina IV]
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOGUE CARD NUMBER A 54 - 7310
Original title:
DE WIJSBEGEERTE DER WETSIDEE
Printed in the United States of America
[pagina XV]
CONTENTS
Page | |
---|---|
FOREWORD (ABREVIATED) TO THE FIRST (DUTCH) EDITION | v |
FOREWORD TO THE SECOND (ENGLISH) EDITION | x |
TRANSLATORS' PREFACE | xii |
CONTENTS | xv |
PART I - PROLEGOMENA
INTRODUCTION - THE FIRST WAY OF A TRANSCENDENTAL CRITIQUE OF PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHT | 3 | |
Meaning as the mode of being of all that is created | 4 | |
The direction of philosophical thought to the totality of meaning implies critical self-reflection | 5 | |
The supposed reduction of the selfhood to an immanent, subjective pole of thought | 6 | |
The transcendence of our selfhood above theoretical thought. The so-called transcendental subject of thought cannot be self-sufficient as a theoretical abstraction | 7 | |
How does philosophical thought attain to the Idea of the totality of meaning? | 7 | |
The Archimedean point of philosophy and the tendency of philosophical thought towards the Origin | 8 | |
The opposition between so-called critical and genetic method is terminologically confusing, because it is not clearly defined in its sense | 9 | |
The restlessness of meaning in the tendency of philosophic thought towards the origin | 11 | |
The three requirements which the Archimedean point must satisfy | 12 | |
The immanence-standpoint in philosophy | 12 | |
The immanence-standpoint does not in itself exclude the so-called metaphysical way to that which transcends human thought | 13 |
[pagina XVI]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
We employ the term immanence-philosophy in the widest possible sense | 13 | |
The inner problematic situation of the immanence-standpoint | 15 | |
Why totality of meaning cannot be found in the coherence of the modal aspects | 15 | |
The Archimedean point as concentration-point for philosophic thought | 16 | |
Does the so-called transcendental subject of thought satisfy the requirements for the Archimedean point? | 16 | |
The theoretical synthesis supposes the modal diversity of meaning of the logical and the non-logical which is its opposite | 18 | |
The pitfall in the conception of the so-called transcendental subject of thought as Archimedean point: cosmic diversity of meaning and diversity in the special logical meaning | 19 | |
Misunderstanding of the intermodal synthesis of meaning as a transcendental-logical one | 19 | |
The necessary religious transcending in the choice of the immanence-standpoint | 20 | |
CHAPTER I - THE TRANSCENDENTAL CRITICISM OF THEORETICAL THOUGHT AND THE CENTRAL SIGNIFICANCE OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL GROUND-IDEA FOR PHILOSOPHY | 22 | |
§ 1 - | The problem of time | 22 |
Rickert's conception of the self-limitation of thought | 23 | |
The immanence of all modal aspects of meaning in time | 24 | |
The influence of the dialectical ground-motives upon the philosophical conception of time | 25 | |
The integral character of cosmic time. The correlation of temporal order and duration, and the subject-object relation in the latter | 28 | |
All structures of temporal reality are structures of cosmic time | 29 | |
The transcendental Idea and the modal concepts of time. The logical aspect of temporal order and duration | 30 | |
No static conception of the supra-temporal. Is the acceptance of a central trans-cosmic time desirable? | 32 | |
The eschatological aspect of cosmic time in faith | 33 | |
Naïve and theoretical experience of time | 33 | |
§ 2 - | The transcendental criticism of theoretical thought and the dogma concerning the autonomy of the latter. The second way to a transcendental criticism of philosophy | 34 |
The dogmatic positing of the autonomy of theoretical thought | 35 |
[pagina XVII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The different views of the autonomy of theoretical thought and the origin of this difference | 35 | |
The dogma concerning the autonomy of theoretical thought as an impediment to philosophical discussion among the various schools | 36 | |
The necessity of a transcendental criticism of the theoretical attitude of thought as such. The difference in principle between transcendent and transcendental criticism | 37 | |
§ 3 - | The first transcendental basic problem of theoretical thought. The ‘gegenstand-relation’ versus the subject-object-relation | 38 |
The antithetical structure of the theoretical attitude of thought in its purely intentional character and the origin of the theoretical problem | 39 | |
A closer confrontation of the naïve attitude with the theoretical | 41 | |
The subject-object-relation in naïve experience | 42 | |
The consequences of ignoring the first transcendental basic problem in the traditional conception as to the relation of body and soul in human nature | 44 | |
§ 4 - | The second transcendental basic problem: the starting-point of theoretical synthesis | 45 |
The impasse of the immanence-standpoint and the source of the theoretical antinomies | 45 | |
The various -isms in the theoretical vision of reality | 46 | |
The problem of the basic denominator for the theoretical comparison and distinction of the modal aspects | 47 | |
The rôle of the -isms in pure mathematics and in logic | 47 | |
Provisional delimitation of the moral aspect | 48 | |
The starting-point of theoretical synthesis in the Kantian critique of knowledge | 49 | |
The problem of the starting-point and the way of critical self-reflection in theoretical thought | 51 | |
§ 5 - | The third transcendental basic problem of the critique of theoretical thought and Kant's transcendental unity of apperception | 52 |
The alleged vicious circle in our transcendental criticism | 56 | |
What is religion? | 57 | |
The impossibility of a phenomenology of religion. The ex-sistent character of the ego as the religious centre of existence | 57 | |
The supra-individual character of the starting-point | 59 | |
The meaning of the central command of love | 60 |
[pagina XVIII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The spirit of community and the religious basic motive | 61 | |
The Greek form-matter-motive and the modern Humanistic motive of nature and freedom | 61 | |
Sin as privatio and as dynamis. No dialectical relation between creation and fall | 63 | |
The dialectical character of the apostate ground-motives. Religious and theoretic dialectic | 64 | |
The uncritical character of the attempts to bridge the religious antithesis in a dialectical starting-point by a theoretical dialectic | 64 | |
The religious dialectic in the scholastic motive of nature and grace | 65 | |
The ascription of the primacy to one of the antithetic components of the dialectical ground-motive | 66 | |
The meaning of each of the antithetic components of a dialectic ground-motive is dependent upon that of the other | 68 | |
§ 6 - | The transcendental ground-idea of philosophy | 68 |
The three transcendental Ideas of theoretical thought, through the medium of which the religious basic motive controls this thought | 68 | |
The triunity of the transcendental ground-Idea | 69 | |
The transcendental critique of theoretical thought and the dogmatic exclusivism of the philosophical schools | 70 | |
The metaphysical-analogical concept of totality and the transcendental Idea of the totality of meaning. Transcendental critique of the metaphysical conception of the analogia entis | 71 | |
The so-called logical formalizing of the concept of totality and the philosophical Idea of totality | 73 | |
The principle of the Origin and the continuity-principle in Cohen's philosophy | 74 | |
Being and Validity and the critical preliminary question as to the meaning of these concepts | 76 | |
Levelling of the modal diversity of meaning in the generic concept rests upon an uncritical misjudgment of the special meaning in the logical aspect | 77 | |
The masking of the transcendental ground-Idea by the so-called dialectical logic. Theodor Litt | 77 | |
Modal diversity and radical identity of meaning. Logical identity has only model meaning. Parmenides | 79 | |
§ 7 - | The transcendental ground-idea as hypothesis of philosophy | 82 |
[pagina XIX]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The theoretical character of the transcendental ground-Idea and its relation to naïve experience | 82 | |
The datum of naïve experience as a philosophical problem | 83 | |
The naïve concept of the thing and the special scientific concept of function | 83 | |
Philosophy, special science, and naïve experience | 84 | |
‘Reflexive’ thought versus ‘objective’ thought in recent philosophy. The confusion of ‘object’ and ‘Gegenstand’ in this opposition | 86 | |
The transcendental ground-Idea as hypothesis of philosophy | 86 | |
The relation of transcendent and transcendental points of views and the original meaning of the transcendental motive | 88 | |
Kant's opinion concerning the transcendental Ideas. Why did Kant fail to conceive of these Ideas as ὑπόϑεσις of his critiques | 89 | |
It was Fichte who tried to remove the difficulties involved in the Kantian dualistic conception | 90 | |
The decline of the transcendental motive in the Marburg methodological logicism, in Litt's conception of reflexive thought, and in Husserl's ‘egology’ | 91 | |
The basic Idea of philosophy remains a subjective ὑπόϑεσις The criterion of truth and relativism | 91 | |
The transcendental limits of philosophy and the criterion of speculative metaphysics | 92 | |
Calvin's verdict against this metaphysics | 93 | |
§ 8 - | The transcendental ground-idea of philosophy as cosmonomic idea (wetsidee) | 93 |
The Origin of this terminology | 93 | |
Objections against the term ‘cosmonomic Idea’ and the grounds for maintaining it | 94 | |
Misunderstanding of the philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea as meaning-idealism | 96 | |
Cosmonomic Idea, modal concept of laws and modal concept of subject and object | 97 | |
The dependence of the modal concepts of law, subject and object upon the cosmonomic Idea | 98 | |
§ 9 - | The symbol of the refraction of light. The cosmic order of time and the cosmological principle of sovereignty in its proper orbit. The modal aspects of reality as modal law-spheres | 99 |
The lex as boundary between the ‘Being’ of God and the ‘meaning’ of the creation | 99 |
[pagina XX]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The logical function of thought in apostasy | 100 | |
The re-formation of the cosmonomic Idea by the central motive of the Christian religion | 101 | |
The modal law-spheres and their sphere-sovereignty | 102 | |
Christian religion does not allow of any absolutizing with respect to its fulness of meaning | 104 | |
Sphere-sovereignty of the modal aspects in their inter-modal coherence of meaning as a philosophical basic problem | 104 | |
Potentiality and actuality in cosmic time | 105 | |
Cosmic time and the refraction of meaning. Why can the totality of meaning disclose itself in time only in refraction and coherence of modalities? | 105 | |
The logical function is not relative in a logical but in a cosmic sense | 106 | |
The elimination of cosmic time-order in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason | 107 | |
§ 10 - | The importance of our cosmonomic idea in respect to the modal concepts of laws and their subjects | 108 |
Modal concepts of the lex and its subject. The subject as subject to laws | 108 | |
The disturbance of the meaning of the concepts of the modal laws and their subjects in the Humanistic immanence-philosophy | 108 | |
Rationalism as absolutizing of the general rule, irrationalism as absolutizing of individual subjectivity | 110 | |
The concept of the subject in the irrationalistic phenomenology and philosophy of existence | 111 | |
The concept of the lex and the subject in ancient Greek thought and its dependence on the Greek form-matter-motive | 112 | |
CHAPTER II - PHILOSOPHY AND LIFE- AND WORLD-VIEW | 114 | |
§ 1 - | The antithetic position of the philosophy of the cosmonomic idea in respect to the immanence-philosophy and the postulate of the historical continuity in philosophical thought contained in the idea of the ‘philosophia perennis’ | 114 |
The basis of cooperation between Christian thought and the different trends of immanence-philosophy | 114 | |
A popular argument against the possibility of Christian science and philosophy | 115 | |
Partial truths are not self-sufficient. Every partial truth is dependent upon truth in its totality of meaning | 116 |
[pagina XXI]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The undeniable states of affairs in the structure of temporal reality | 116 | |
The idea of the perennial philosophy | 117 | |
How is the idea of the ‘philosophia perennis’ to be understood? Philosophic thought and historical development | 118 | |
What is permanent, and what is subjected to the historical development of thought. The scholastic standpoint of accommodation forever condemned | 119 | |
The conception of the antithesis of standpoints in the immanence-philosophy as ‘Weltanschauungslehre’ (theory of life- and world-views) | 120 | |
The consequence of our transcendental critique for the history of philosophy | 122 | |
The only possible ultimate antithesis in philosophy | 123 | |
§ 2 - | The distinction between philosophy and life- and world-view and the criterion | 124 |
The boundaries between philosophy and a life- and world-view as seen from the immanence-standpoint. Disagreement as to the criterion | 124 | |
Life- and world-view as an ‘individual impression of life’, Theodor Litt and Georg Simmel | 126 | |
The relationship as seen from the Christian transcendence-standpoint | 127 | |
§ 3 - | The neutrality-postulate and the ‘theory of life and world-views’ | 128 |
Rickert's defence of the neutrality-postulate | 129 | |
Criticism of the fundamentals of the ‘Weltanschauungslehre’ | 134 | |
Immanent antinomy in Rickert's philosophy of values | 135 | |
The test of the transcendental ground-Idea | 136 | |
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea does not judge about matters over which no judgment belongs to man, but leads to fundamental self-criticism of the thinker | 137 | |
§ 4 - | Sequel: The pretended self-guarantee of theoretical truth | 138 |
Litt's argument concerning the self-guarantee of theoretical truth | 138 | |
Critique of Litt's conception | 141 | |
The first pitfall in Litt's demonstration: the unconditional character of the ‘transcendental cogito’ | 142 | |
The second pitfall: the opposition of transcendental thought and full reality | 143 |
[pagina XXII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The ‘self-refutation of scepticism’ reduced to its true proportion | 144 | |
The test of the transcendental ground-Idea | 147 | |
§ 5 - | The transcendental ground-idea and the meaning of truth | 148 |
The impossibility of an authentic religiously neutral theory of the life- and world-views. The concept of truth is never purely theoretical with respect to its meaning | 148 | |
Immanence-philosophy recognizes no norm of truth above its transcendental ground-Idea | 150 | |
The distinction between theoretical and a-theoretical judgments. The inner contradiction of a restriction of the validity of truth to the former | 151 | |
Theoretical and non-theoretical judgments. The latter are never a-logical, but merely non-‘gegenständlich’ | 153 | |
Litt's distinction between theoretical and ‘weltanschauliche’ truth and the self-refutation of this distinction in the sense in which Litt intends it | 154 | |
The inner contradiction of this dualism. The meaninglessness of judgments, which are alleged not to be subjected to the norm of truth | 154 | |
§ 6 - | Closer determination of the relation between philosophy and a life- and world-view | 156 |
The life- and world-view is no system and cannot be made a system without affecting its essence | 157 | |
What is the meaning of the concept ‘universal-validity’? The Kantian conception is determined by the critical Humanist immanence-standpoint | 158 | |
The possibility of universally valid judgments depends on the universal supra-subjective validity of the structural laws of human experience | 160 | |
The universal validity of a correct judgment of perception | 161 | |
The criterion of universal validity of a judgment concerning supra-theoretical states of affairs and the unconditional validity of the religious law of concentration of human experience | 162 | |
The so-called ‘transcendental consciousness’ as hypostatization of theoretical human thought in its general apostasy from the fulness of meaning of truth | 163 | |
Impurity of the opposition ‘universal-validity’ and individuality as a contradictory one | 164 | |
Neither life- and world-view, nor philosophy is to be understood individualistically | 164 |
[pagina XXIII]
PART II - THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE BASIC ANTINOMY IN THE COSMONOMIC IDEA OF HUMANISTIC IMMANENCE-PHILOSOPHY
Page | ||
---|---|---|
CHAPTER I - THE BASIC STRUCTURE OF THE HUMANISTIC TRANSCENDENTAL GROUND-IDEA AND THE INTRINSIC POLARITY BETWEEN THE CLASSICAL SCIENCE-IDEAL AND THE IDEAL OF PERSONALITY | 169 | |
§ 1 - | Introduction. Humanistic philosophy and the humanistic view of life and the world | 169 |
The undermining of the personal sense of responsibility in the religious commitment | 170 | |
The synthetic standpoint of Thomistic philosophy and the disruption of this synthesis by the nominalism of late scholasticism | 172 | |
The Aristotelian-Thomistic philosophy and medieval culture | 173 | |
The integral and radical character of the religious ground-motive of creation, the fall and redemption in the Biblical sense | 173 | |
Sin and the dialectical conception of guilt in Greek and Humanistic philosophy | 175 | |
Once again the inner reformation of philosophic thought | 176 | |
The speculative logos-theory | 177 | |
Philosophy as ancilla theologiae in Augustinian scholasticism | 177 | |
The scholastic character of Augustine's cosmonomic Idea | 178 | |
The entrance of the dialectical ground-motive of nature and grace in Christian scholasticism | 179 | |
Creation as a natural truth in Thomas' theologia naturalis | 180 | |
The elimination of the integral and radical meaning of the Biblical motive of creation in Thomas' metaphysics | 180 | |
The elimination of the radical meaning of fall and redemption. The neo-Platonic Augustinian trend in Thomas' natural theology | 181 | |
The Aristotelian cosmonomic Idea | 181 | |
The content of the Thomistic cosmonomic Idea | 182 | |
The intrinsic dialectic of the scholastic basic motive of nature and grace and the nominalism of the fourteenth century | 183 | |
The ‘primacy of the will’ in the nominalistic school of thought versus the ‘primacy of the intellect’ in the realistic metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas. There is no essential connection between realism and the primacy of the intellect | 185 |
[pagina XXIV]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The primacy of the will in the cosmonomic Idea of Augustine | 185 | |
The potestas Dei absoluta in Duns Scotus and William of Occam | 186 | |
The nominalistic conception of the potestas Dei absoluta entirely contrary to its own intention places God's Creative Will under the boundary-line of the lex | 187 | |
The nominalistic critique effectuated a radical disruption between the Christian and pagan motives in medieval scholasticism | 187 | |
Secularization of nominalism in late scholasticism | 188 | |
§ 2 - | The rise of humanistic philosophical thought | 188 |
The collapse of the ecclesiastically unified culture | 189 | |
A closer consideration of the religious ground-motive of Humanism: the motive of nature and freedom | 190 | |
The ambiguity of the Humanistic motive of freedom | 190 | |
The new ideal of personality of the Renaissance | 191 | |
The motive of the domination of nature and the ambiguity of the nature-motive | 192 | |
The πέϱας and the ἄπειϱον. The antithesis with the ancient ideal of life | 194 | |
The Cartesian ‘Cogito’ in contra-distinction to the theoretical nous as the Archimedian point of Greek metaphysics | 195 | |
There is no relationship between Descartes' and Augustine's Archimedean point. The misconception of the Jansenists of Port Royal on this issue | 196 | |
The connection between Descartes' methodological scepticism and the discovery of analytical geometry. The creation-motive in the Cartesian ‘cogito’ | 197 | |
The polar tension between the ideal of personality and the ideal of science in the basic structure of the Humanistic transcendental Idea | 198 | |
The tendency towards infinity in Giordiano Bruno's pantheism | 199 | |
§ 3 - | The postulate of continuity in the humanistic science-ideal and the basic antinomy in the humanistic cosmonomic idea | 200 |
The concept of substance in the new Humanistic metaphysics is quite different from the Aristotelian-Thomistic or Platonic one | 201 | |
The lex continui in Leibniz and the Marburg school of Neo-Kantians | 204 | |
The fundamental antinomy in the basic structure of the Humanistic transcendental ground-Idea | 204 |
[pagina XXV]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The supposed solution of this antinomy in transcendental thought | 205 | |
The tendency of continuity in the freedom-motive of the ideal of personality | 206 | |
§ 4 - | A diorama of the dialectical development of humanistic philosophy after Kant. The process of religious uprooting and the actuality of our transcendental critique | 207 |
The origination of a new historical science-ideal out of an irrationalistic and universalistic turn in the freedom-motive | 207 | |
The polar tension between the historistic ideal of science and the idealistic dialectic of Hegel's freedom-idealism | 208 | |
The rise of positivistic sociology and the transformation of the historical method of thought into a natural scientific one | 209 | |
The transformation of historicism into naturalistic evolutionism | 210 | |
The first expression of the spiritual disintegrating process in Historicism. Nietzsche's religion of power | 210 | |
The rôle of neo-Kantianism and neo-Hegelianism in the crisis of historicism | 212 | |
The classic ideal of science and the development of 20th century physics. The neo-positivism of the Vienna school | 212 | |
Husserl's eidetic logic and phenomenology | 213 | |
The attitude of decline in Spengler's philosophy of history and in Humanistic existentialism | 214 | |
The actuality of our transcendental critique of theoretical thought | 215 | |
CHAPTER II - THE IDEAL OF PERSONALITY AND THE NATURAL SCIENCE-IDEAL IN THE FIRST TYPES OF THEIR MUTUAL POLAR TENSION UNDER THE PRIMACY OF THE FORMER | 216 | |
§ 1 - | The naturalistic-monistic and the dualistic type of transcendental ground-idea under the primacy of the science-ideal. Its connection with the pessimistic and semi-pessimistic view of life | 216 |
The conflict between Descartes and Hobbes as the first expression of the basic antinomy in the Humanistic cosmonomic Idea | 216 | |
Hobbes' pessimism and its connection with his ascription of primacy to the science-ideal. Virtue and necessity in Macchiavelli | 217 |
[pagina XXVI]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The dualism between thought and extension in Descartes | 218 | |
The background of the ideal of personality in this dualism | 218 | |
The metaphysical problem concerning the relation between soul and body acquires a new significance in the light of the transcendental Humanist ground-Idea | 219 | |
The deeper ground of Descartes' partial indeterminism | 220 | |
The antinomy in Hobbes' naturalistic conception of thought in the light of the deterministic ideal of science. The ideae innatae of Descartes | 221 | |
§ 2 - | The mathematical-idealistic type of humanist transcendental ground-idea | 223 |
The supposed Thomistic-Aristotelian traits in Leibniz' philosophy | 223 | |
The secularization of the motive of nature and grace in Leibniz' philosophy | 226 | |
The refinement of the postulate of continuity in the science-ideal by means of Leibniz' mathematical concept of function. | ||
The discovery of differential and integral calculus | 227 | |
The two roots of Leibniz' philosophy. The misunderstanding in Schmalenbach concerning the Calvinistic origin of Leibniz' individualism | 229 | |
Leibniz' concept of force and the motive of activity in the ideal of personality | 230 | |
Primacy of the mathematical science-ideal in Leibniz' transcendental ground-Idea | 232 | |
Leibniz' Humanistic theism | 234 | |
Logicization of the dynamical tendency in the ideal of personality | 234 | |
Leibniz' intellectual determinism and his doctrine of innate Ideas in the light of the lex continui | 236 | |
§ 3 - | The moderate nominalism in Leibniz' conception of ideas. The idea as symbol of relations and as the concept of law of the rationalistic ideal of science | 240 |
The apparent fight against nominalism in the third book of Leibniz' ‘Nouveaux Essais’ | 241 | |
Leibniz' nominalistic standpoint in his treatise concerning the philosophical style of Nizolius (1670) | 244 | |
The notion of the logical alphabet and the symbolical conception of ideas | 245 |
[pagina XXVII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
§ 4 - | The modal aspects of reality as modi of mathematical thought | 247 |
Phenomenon and noumenon in Leibniz' metaphysics; ‘verités de raison’ and ‘verités de fait’. Leibniz' mathematical idealism | 249 | |
Spinoza and Leibniz. Wolff's eradication of the distinction between necessary and contingent truths | 250 | |
§ 5 - | The basic antinomy in the humanistic transcendental ground-idea in its mathematical-idealistic type and the relation of this type to the optimistic life- and world-view | 252 |
The Theodicy with its apparent reconciliation of the ideals of science and personality. The optimism of Leibniz | 252 | |
The deceptive formulation of the polar tension between the ideal of science and that of personality in the terminology of the Christian doctrine of faith | 253 | |
The basic antinomy in the Humanistic transcendental ground-Idea acquires in Leibniz the mathematical form of the antinomy of the actual infinity | 255 | |
‘Metaphysical evil’ as an eternal necessary truth in creative mathematical thought | 256 | |
Metaphysical evil as the root of physical and moral evil (sin!) | 258 | |
How Leibniz attempted to resolve metaphysical evil into the continuity of infinite mathematical analysis | 259 | |
Leibniz and Bayle | 260 | |
CHAPTER III - THE IDEAL OF PERSONALITY AND THE IDEAL OF SCIENCE IN THE CRITICAL TRANSITION TO THE PRIMACY OF THE IDEAL OF PERSONALITY | 262 | |
§ 1 - | The psychological turn in the science-ideal and its transcendental idea of origin | 262 |
The psychological turn in the ideal of science in empiricism since Locke | 262 | |
The inner antinomy in Locke's psychological dualism | 264 | |
Locke maintains the mathematical science-ideal with its creation-motive, though in a limited sphere | 267 | |
The tendency toward the origin in Locke's opposition to the innate Ideas, and the transcendental Idea of origin in Locke's epistemology | 268 | |
The distinction between the knowledge of facts and the knowledge of the necessary relations between concepts | 269 |
[pagina XXVIII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
§ 2 - | The monistic psychological type of the humanistic transcendental ground-idea under the primacy of the science-ideal | 271 |
The psychologized conception of the science-ideal in Hume. Once again the nominalistic trait in the ideal of science | 272 | |
Hume and Pyrrhonic scepticism. Sextus Empiricus | 275 | |
Sceptical doubt in Hume, as in Descartes, has only methodological significance | 275 | |
The criterion of truth | 276 | |
The natural and philosophical relations. The laws of association | 277 | |
§ 3 - | The transition of the creation-motive in the science-ideal to psychological thought. Hume's criticism of mathematics | 280 |
Contradictory interpretations of Hume's criticism of mathematics | 280 | |
The method of solving this controversy | 282 | |
Hume drew the full consequences of his ‘psychologistic’ nominalism with respect to mathematics | 283 | |
Hume's psychologistic concept of space. Space as a complex of coloured points (minima sensibilia) | 284 | |
Psychologizing of the mathematical concept of equality | 285 | |
The position of arithmetic in Hume's sensationalism | 287 | |
Hume's retrogression into the Lockian conception of mathematics remains completely inexplicable on the sensationalistic basis of his system | 288 | |
§ 4 - | The dissolution of the ideals of science and of personality by the psychologistic critique | 289 |
Hume's criticism of the concept of substance and his interpretation of naïve experience | 289 | |
The creative function of imagination and the way in which the creation-motive of the Humanistic ideal of science is transmitted to psychological thought | 292 | |
Hume destroys the metaphysical foundation of the rationalist ideal of personality | 294 | |
The radical self-dissolution of the ideals of science and of personality in Hume's philosophy | 296 | |
§ 5 - | Continuation: The criticism of the principle of causality as a critique of experience | 297 |
The problem pertaining to the necessary connection of cause and effect is to Hume the problem of the origin of natural laws as such | 298 |
[pagina XXIX]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
According to Hume, the law of causality is only to be maintained as a psychical law of association. Nevertheless, every legitimate foundation for the ideal of science in a mathematical physical sense is lacking | 299 | |
The way in which Hume's Critique finally undermines the foundations of his own psychological science-ideal | 299 | |
Hume disregards the synthesis of logical and psychical meaning in his psychological basic denominator | 300 | |
§ 6 - | The prelude to the shifting of the primacy to the ideal of personality | 302 |
The extension of the psychologized science-ideal over the modal boundaries of meaning of the aesthetic, juridical, moral and faith-aspects | 302 | |
The cooperation between the associations of ideas and those of passions | 304 | |
The way in which Hume's psychologized ideal of science destroys the conception of freedom of the will in the sense of the mathematical ideal of science | 305 | |
The prelude to the shift of primacy to the ideal of personality | 306 | |
Hume withdraws morality from the science-ideal. Primacy of the moral feeling | 307 | |
Hume's attack upon the rationalistic theory of Humanist natural law and upon its construction of the social contract. Vico and Montesquieu | 310 | |
§ 7 - | The crisis in the conflict between the ideal of science and that of personality in Rousseau | 313 |
Rousseau's religion of sentiment and his estrangement from Hume | 316 | |
Optimism and pessimism in their new relation in Rousseau | 317 | |
Locke and Rousseau. The contrast between innate human rights and inalienable rights of the citizen | 318 | |
The ideal of personality acquires the primacy in Rousseau's construction of the social contract | 319 | |
The antinomy between the natural rights of man and the rights of citizen. Rousseau's attempt to solve it | 321 | |
The origin of this antinomy is again to be found in the tension between the ideal of science and that of personality | 323 |
[pagina XXX]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
CHAPTER IV - THE LINE OF DEMARCATION BETWEEN THE IDEALS OF SCIENCE AND OF PERSONALITY IN KANT. THE (CRITICAL) DUALIST IDEALISTIC TYPE OF TRANSCENDENTAL GROUND-IDEA UNDER THE PRIMACY OF THE HUMANIST IDEAL OF PERSONALITY | 325 | |
§ 1 - | Introduction. The misconception of Kant's transcendental idealism as the philosophic expression of the spirit of reformation | 325 |
Kroner's view of the relation of Kant's transcendental idealism to the Christian religion | 325 | |
Is Kant the philosopher of the Reformation? Przywara | 326 | |
The Idea of freedom as both the religious totality and origin of meaning: Höningswald | 328 | |
§ 2 - | The development of the conflict between the ideal of personality and that of science in the first phase of Kant's thought up until his inaugural oration of 1770 | 330 |
The motives of the preceding Humanistic philosophy. The manner in which Kant wrestles with their mutual tension. The influence of Pietism | 330 | |
In his natural scientific conception, Kant remained a faithful adherent of the ideal of science; his reverence for the spirit of the ‘Enlightenment’ | 331 | |
The influence of Rousseau and Hume | 332 | |
Kant's first period: Kant as an independent supporter of the metaphysics of Leibniz and Wolff. The primacy of the mathematical science-ideal in the first conception of his transcendental ground-Idea | 335 | |
Kant's second period: the methodological line of demarcation between mathematics and metaphysics. The influence of Newton and English psychologism | 336 | |
The rupture between the metaphysics of the science-ideal and moral philosophy in this period of Kant's thought | 338 | |
Influence of Crusius | 339 | |
Third period: the dominating influence of Hume and Rousseau. Complete emancipation of the ideal of personality from the metaphysics of the science-ideal | 340 | |
The transitional phase in Kant's thought until 1770 | 341 | |
The problem of the mathematical antinomies. Leibniz' and Newton's conception of space and time | 343 | |
§ 3 - | The further development of this conflict and the origination of the real critical philosophy | 344 |
[pagina XXXI]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The separation of understanding and sensibility in Kant's inaugural address of 1770 | 344 | |
The development of Kant's new conception of the ideal of personality. Earlier optimism is replaced by a radical pessimism with respect to the sensory nature of man | 346 | |
The new conception of the ideal of personality as ὑπόϑεσις in the transition to the critical standpoint | 351 | |
The ‘Dialectic of Pure Reason’ as the heart of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason | 353 | |
§ 4 - | The antinomy between the ideal of science and that of personality in the critique of pure reason | 354 |
The deepest tendencies of Kant's Copernican revolution in epistemology are brought to light by the ascription of primacy to the ideal of personality resulting in a new form of the Humanistic ground-Idea | 355 | |
The dualistic type of the Kantian transcendental ground-Idea | 357 | |
In Kant's transcendental dualistic ground-Idea the basic antinomy between the ideals of science and of personality assumes a form which was to become the point of departure for all the subsequent attempts made by post-Kantian idealism to conquer this dualism | 358 | |
The expression of this dualism in the antithesis of natural laws and norms | 359 | |
The form-matter schema in Kant's epistemology as an expression of the inner antinomy of his dualistic transcendental ground-Idea | 360 | |
The function of the transcendental Ideas of theoretical reason | 362 | |
Kant's shifting of the Archimedean point of Humanist philosophy is clearly evident from his critique of metaphysical psychology, in which self-consciousness had identified itself with mathematical thought | 365 | |
Kant's criticism of ‘rational cosmology’ (natural metaphysics) in the light of the transcendental trend of the cosmological Ideas | 367 | |
The intervention of the ideal of personality in Kant's solution of the so-called dynamical antinomies and the insoluble antinomy in Kant's dualistic transcendental ground-Idea | 369 | |
Within the cadre of Kant's transcendental ground-Idea the natural ‘Ding an sich’ can no longer be maintained. The depreciation of the theoretical Idea of God | 372 | |
§ 5 - | The development of the basic antinomy in the ‘critique of practical reason’ | 372 |
Autos and nomos in Kant's Idea of autonomy | 373 |
[pagina XXXII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The dualistic division between the ideal of science and the ideal of personality delivers the latter into the hands of a logical formalism | 374 | |
The precise definition of the principle of autonomy through the Idea of personality as ‘end in itself’ | 376 | |
In the application of Kant's categorical imperative to concrete actions, the dualism between ‘nature’ (ideal of science) and ‘freedom’ (ideal of personality) becomes an antinomy | 378 | |
Kant's characterization of Leibniz' conception of free personality as ‘automaton spirituale’ | 380 | |
Kroner's conception of the origin of the antinomy in Kant's doctrine of ‘pure will’ as ‘causa noumenon’ | 381 | |
The antinomy between nature and freedom in Kant's concept of the highest good | 381 | |
Kant formulates the antinomy between the ideal of science and that of personality as it is implied in the concept of the highest good as the ‘antinomy of practical reason’ | 383 | |
In Kant's Idea of God the ideal of personality dominates the ideal of science | 384 | |
§ 6 - | The development of the basic antinomy in the critique of judgment | 385 |
The attempt to resolve the dualism between the ideal of science and that of personality in the Critique of Judgment. The problem of individuality | 385 | |
Kant's rationalistic conception of individuality | 387 | |
The idea of teleology in nature | 388 | |
The law of specification as the regulative principle of the transcendental faculty of judgment for the contemplation of nature | 389 | |
The reason why the ‘Critique of Judgment’ cannot resolve the basic discord in Kant's Archimedean point | 390 | |
The same antinomy which intrinsically destroys the Idea of the ‘homo noumenon’ recurs in the principle of teleological judgment | 393 | |
The fictitious character of the teleological view of nature follows directly from Kant's transcendental ground-Idea | 395 | |
The origin of the antinomy of the faculty of teleological judgment in the light of Kant's cosmonomic Idea | 396 | |
The basic antinomy between the ideals of science and personality in Kant is everywhere crystallized in the form-matter schema. A synopsis of the development of this antinomy in the three Critiques | 400 |
[pagina XXXIII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
Kant's dualistic transcendental ground-Idea lacks an unequivocal Archimedean point and an unequivocal Idea of the totality of meaning | 402 | |
CHAPTER V - THE TENSION BETWEEN THE IDEAL OF SCIENCE AND THAT OF PERSONALITY IN THE INDENTITY-PHILOSOPHY OF POST-KANTIAN FREEDOM-IDEALISM | 403 | |
§ 1 - | The transitional period between critical idealism and monistic freedom-idealism. From Maimon to Fichte | 403 |
Maimon's attempt at a solution of the antinomy in Kant's form-matter scheme by means of Leibniz' principle of continuity | 404 | |
Maimon's falling away from the veritable transcendental motive. How the transcendental Idea loses for him its direction toward Kant's ideal of personality | 405 | |
Maimon's mathematical Criticism and the Marburg school among the Neo-Kantians | 406 | |
The problem as to the relation between the universal and the particular in knowledge within the domain of Kant's apriori forms of consciousness. Maimon's cosmonomic Idea | 408 | |
In the explanation of his ‘principle of determinability’ Maimon starts from three fundamentally different ways in which thought can combine a manifold of ‘objects of consciousness’ into a logical unity | 409 | |
The break between form and sensory matter of knowledge. Maimon's later critical scepticism with respect to Kant's concept of experience | 410 | |
Within the limits of the critical standpoint, the mathematical science-ideal appears unable to overcome Kant's dualism between sensibility and reason | 412 | |
§ 2 - | The continuity-postulate in the new conception of the ideal of personality and the genesis of the dialectical philosophy in Fichte's first ‘theoretische wissenschaftslehre’ (1794) | 413 |
The ground-motive of Fichte's first ‘Wissenschaftslehre’. The creative moment in the personality-ideal | 413 | |
The Archimedean point in Fichte's transcendental ground-Idea | 415 | |
Fichte's ‘absolute ego’ as origin and totality of all cosmic diversity of meaning is nothing but the hypostatization of the moral function | 416 | |
Fichte's attempt at a transcendental deduction of the Kantian forms of thought from the self-consciousness | 418 |
[pagina XXXIV]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
Dialectical thought, dominated by the ideal of personality, usurps the task of the cosmic order | 420 | |
To Fichte the ‘absolute ego’ remains outside the dialectical system. The Idea of the absolute ego as ethical task | 422 | |
Fichte attempts to give an account of the possibility of theoretical knowledge by referring the latter to the selfhood. Why this attempt cannot succeed on Fichte's immanence-standpoint | 423 | |
Transcendental deduction of the Kantian categories of relation from self-consciousness. The science-ideal is here derived from the ideal of personality | 424 | |
The domination of the continuity-postulate of the ideal of personality. The Humanist transcendental ground-Idea in its transcendental monist-moralistic type | 426 | |
Productive imagination is to Fichte the creative origin of sensory matter | 426 | |
Fichte conceives of the productive imagination as an unconscious function of reason | 429 | |
In his concept of the productive imagination, Fichte does not penetrate to pre-theoretical cosmic self-consciousness but remains involved in Kant's functionalistic view of knowledge | 431 | |
Fichte's doctrine of the productive imagination and Heidegger's interpretation of Kant | 434 | |
§ 3 - | The tension between the ideals of science and personality in Fichte's ‘praktische wissenschaftslehre’ (1794) | 435 |
Fichte refers the impulse toward sensory experience to the moral function of personality, in which the ideal of personality is concentrated | 436 | |
The infinite and unlimited ego as moral striving. Elimination also of Kant's practical concept of substance. The ego as infinite creative activity is identified with Kant's categorical imperative | 437 | |
The ‘fatalism’ so keenly opposed by Fichte is nothing but the science-ideal of the ‘Aufklärung’, dominating the ideal of personality | 440 | |
The dialectical line of thought of the practical doctrine of science: feeling, intuition, longing, approbation, absolute impulse (categorical imperative) | 442 | |
The categorical imperative as the absolute impulse that is grounded in itself | 446 | |
Fichte's dithyramb on the ideal of personality: ‘Ueber die Würde des Menschen’ (On the dignity of man) | 447 |
[pagina XXXV]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The passion for power in Fichte's ideal of personality. The science-ideal converts itself into a titanic ideal of culture | 448 | |
The antinomy between the science-ideal and personality-ideal has actually converted itself in Fichte's first period into an antinomy between Idea and sense within the personality-ideal itself | 450 | |
CHAPTER VI - THE VICTORY OF THE IRRATIONALIST OVER THE RATIONALIST CONCEPTION OF THE HUMANISTIC TRANSCENDENTAL GROUND-IDEA. THE IDEAL OF PERSONALITY IN ITS IRRATIONALIST TURN IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF LIFE | 451 | |
§ 1 - | The transition to irrationalism in Fichte's third period under the influence of the movement of the ‘sturm und drang’ (‘storm and stress’) | 451 |
Fichte's relation to ‘Sturm und Drang’ | 451 | |
The irrationalist view of the individuality of genius. The irrationalist turn in the ideal of personality | 453 | |
Tension between the irrationalist conception of freedom and the science-ideal in its Leibnizian form in Herder. The antinomy is sought in ‘life’ itself. The Faust- and the Prometheus-motif | 453 | |
The irrationalist Idea of humanity and the appreciation of individuality in history | 454 | |
Fichte's third period and the influence of Jacobi. Transcendental philosophy in contrast with life-experience. The primacy of life and feeling | 455 | |
Hegel as opposed to the philosophy of life and feeling | 457 | |
Kant's sensory matter of experience is now the ‘true reality’ to Fichte | 457 | |
Recognition of the individual value of the empirical as such. Fichte's estimation of individuality contrasted with that of Kant. Individualizing of the categorical imperative | 460 | |
No radical irrationalism in Fichte's third period | 461 | |
§ 2 - | Aesthetic irrationalism in the humanistic ideal of personality. The ideal of the ‘beautiful soul’. Elaboration of the irrationalist freedom-motive in the modern philosophy of life and its polar tension with the science-ideal | 462 |
Schiller and Kant's ‘Critique of aesthetic Judgment’. Aesthetic idealism. The influence of Shaftesbury | 462 | |
The ideal of ‘the beautiful soul’ | 463 |
[pagina XXXVI]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The ‘morality of genius’ in early Romanticism | 465 | |
The tension of the ideals of science and personality in Nietzsche's development. Biologizing of the science-ideal (Darwin) | 465 | |
The relationship of αὐτός and νόμος in the irrationalist ideal of personality. Dialectical character of the philosophy of life. Modern dialectical phenomenology | 466 | |
The types of the irrationalist cosmonomic Idea of Humanistic thought | 467 | |
§ 3 - | The genesis of a new concept of science from the humanistic ideal of personality in its irrationalist types. Fichte's fourth period | 467 |
Orientation of a new science-ideal to the science of history | 468 | |
Fichte in his fourth period and the South-West-German school of Neo-Kantianism | 469 | |
Hegel's supposed ‘rationalism’ | 470 | |
‘Intellectual intuition’ in Schelling | 471 | |
Hegel's new dialectical logic and its historical orientation | 472 | |
The problem of the ‘Realität der Geisterwelt’ (reality of the world of spirits) | 473 | |
Trans-personalist turn in the ideal of personality. The new conception of the ‘ordo ordinans’ in Fichte's pantheistic metaphysics | 474 | |
Fichte's basic denominator for the aspects of meaning becomes historical in character. Fichte's philosophy of history | 476 | |
Natural individuality must be annihilated in the historical process by the individuality of the spirit | 478 | |
Individuality and Society | 478 | |
Abandonment of the Critical form-matter schema | 479 | |
Fichte's logic of historical thought | 481 | |
Fichte's new historical concept of time | 485 | |
In the ‘Staatslehre’ of 1813, Fichte anticipates the ‘cultural-historical’ method of the South-West-German school of Neo-Kantianism. The synthesis of nature and freedom in the concept of the ‘free force’ | 486 | |
The ‘hidden conformity to law’ of historical development. The irrationalist concept of the law | 488 | |
Irrationalizing of the divine world-plan | 489 | |
The concept of the ‘highly gifted people’ (das geniale Volk) | 491 | |
The inner antinomies in this irrationalist logic of history | 492 |
[pagina XXXVII]
Page | |
---|---|
Law and individuality | 493 |
The ‘historical nationality’ as ‘true reality’ contrasted with the state as conceptual abstraction | 494 |
PART III - CONCLUSION AND TRANSITION TO THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE POSITIVE CONTENTS OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE COSMONOMIC IDEA
CHAPTER I - THE ANTITHETICAL AND SYNTHETICAL STANDPOINTS IN CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT | 499 | |
§ 1 - | A systematic presentation of the antithesis between the basic structure of the christian and that of the various types of humanistic transcendental ground-idea | 499 |
Schema of the basic structure and the polar types of the Humanistic cosmonomic Idea, in confrontation with the Christian ground-Idea | 501 | |
§ 2 - | The attempts to synthesize christian faith with immanence-philosophy before and after the reformation | 508 |
The consequences of the synthetic standpoint for Christian doctrine and for the study of philosophy in patristic and scholastic thought | 508 | |
The cleft between ‘faith’ and ‘thought’ is only a cleft between the Christian faith and immanence-philosophy | 509 | |
The false conception concerning the relationship between Christian revelation and science. Accommodated immanence-philosophy as ancilla theologiae | 510 | |
The consequence of the Reformation for scientific thought | 511 | |
The after-effect of the nominalistic dualism in Luther's spiritualistic distinction between the Law and the Gospel | 511 | |
The scholastic philosophy of Melanchton. Melanchton and Leibniz | 513 | |
Melanchton did not break radically with immanence-philosophy | 515 | |
Why a radical Christian philosophy can only develop in the line of Calvin's religious starting-point | 515 | |
The cosmonomic Idea of Calvin versus the Aristotelian-Thomistic one | 518 | |
Calvin's Idea of the Law versus Brunner's irrationalistic and dualistic standpoint | 519 | |
There is no dualism between ‘gratia communis’ and ‘gratia particularis’ | 523 |
[pagina XXXVIII]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
Abraham Kuyper and his often misunderstood idea of antithesis | 523 | |
Why I reject the term ‘Calvinistic philosophy’ | 524 | |
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea and Blondelism | 525 | |
The significance of the philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea for a philosophic contact between the different schools | 526 | |
CHAPTER II - THE SYSTEMATIC PLAN OF OUR FURTHER INVESTIGATIONS AND A CLOSER EXAMINATION OF THE RELATION OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE COSMONOMIC IDEA TO THE SPECIAL SCIENCES | 528 | |
§ 1 - | The so-called divisions of systematic philosophy in the light of the transcendental ground-idea | 528 |
The fundamental significance of the transcendental ground-Idea for all attempts made in Humanistic immanence-philosophy to classify the problems of philosophy | 528 | |
Windelband's opinion concerning the necessity of dividing philosophy into a theoretical and a practical section | 531 | |
The distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy in Greek thought | 532 | |
The sophistic distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy in the light of the Greek motive of form and matter | 533 | |
The axiological turn of this distinction. The primacy of theoretical philosophy versus the primacy of practical philosophy | 536 | |
The primacy of practical knowledge in the naturalistic-nominalistic trends of Greek immanence-philosophy | 538 | |
In Greek immanence-philosophy, the necessity of ascribing primacy to the theoretical or to the practical reason is connected with the dialectical form-matter motive | 539 | |
Why we cannot divide philosophy into a theoretical and a practical | 540 | |
§ 2 - | The systematic development of the philosophy of the cosmonomic idea in accordance with indissolubly cohering themata | 541 |
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea does not recognize any dualistic division of philosophy. The themata develop the same philosophical basic problem in moments which are united in the transcendental ground-Idea, in its relation to the different structures of cosmic time. These moments are inseparably linked together | 542 |
[pagina XXXIX]
Page | ||
---|---|---|
The philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea does not recognize any other theoretical foundation than the transcendental critique of philosophical thought | 543 | |
§ 3 - | A closer examination of the relationship between philosophy and the special sciences | 545 |
The separation of philosophy and the special sciences from the standpoint of modern Humanism | 546 | |
The intrinsic untenability of a separation between science and philosophy | 548 | |
The impossibility of drawing a line of demarcation between philosophical and scientific thought in mathematics, in order to make this special science autonomous with respect to philosophy | 549 | |
The positivistic-nominalistic conception of the merely technical character of constructive scientific concepts and methods | 550 | |
The positivistic view of reality versus the jural facts | 551 | |
The modal-functional and the typical structures of reality | 552 | |
The absolutization of the concept of function and the illegitimate introduction of a specific structural concept of individuality as a functional one | 555 | |
The dependence of empirical sciences upon the typical structures of individuality. The revolution of physics in the 20th century | 556 | |
The defence of the autonomy of the special sciences from the so-called critical-realist standpoint | 559 | |
Experiments do not disclose a static reality, given independently of logical thought; rather they point to the solution of questions concerning an aspect of reality which, under the direction of theoretical thought, is involved in a process of enrichment and opening of its meaning | 561 | |
The appeal to reality in scientific investigation is never philosophically and religiously neutral. Historicism in science | 562 | |
The conflict between the functionalistic-mechanistic, the neo-vitalistic and holistic trends in modern biology | 564 |