A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 1. The Necessary Presuppositions of Philosophy
(1969)–H. Dooyeweerd– Auteursrechtelijk beschermd
[pagina 451]
| |
Chapter VI
| |
Fichte's relation to ‘Sturm und Drang’.Fichte's relations with the so-called ‘Sturm und Drang’ have recently been examined in detail by LeonGa naar voetnoot1, BergmannGa naar voetnoot2, GelpckeGa naar voetnoot3 and others. Gelpcke sees from the very beginning in Fichte the | |
[pagina 452]
| |
influence of such typical representatives of this movement as Lavater, Hamann and Jacobi operative, even before he was taken up with Kantian critical idealism. The titanic activity-motive, the strong voluntaristic tendency, characteristic of Fichte's philosophy, in all the phases of its development, and which signally differentiates it from the more static Kantian system, shows indeed a veritable congeniality of spirit with the deepest motives of ‘Sturm und Drang’, glorifying the ‘activity of genius’. The activistic ideal of personality permeates all expressions of this transition-period and concentrates itself, as it were, in Goethe's Faust, with its typical utterance: ‘Im Anfang war die Tat (‘In the beginning was the deed’). ‘Sturm und Drang’, as Gelpcke observes, finds its artistic form of expression in the ‘ego-drama’. Activity and selfhood are the two poles in this world of thought. The ideal ‘ego’ is absolutized in a limitless subjectivism and becomes elevated to the rank of genius possessing in itself the perfectly individual moral measure of its action, bound to no general norm. In the foreword to his ‘Räuber’, Schiller has given the following expression to this ingenious subjectivism: ‘The law did not yet form a single great man, but freedom hatches colossosses and extremities’Ga naar voetnoot1. In his ‘Sokratische Denkwürdigkeiten’ (1759)Ga naar voetnoot2 Hamann expressed the same idea in the following form: ‘What replaces in Homer the ignorance of the rules of art which an Aristotle invented, and what in a Shakespeare the ignorance or violation of these critical laws? Genius, is the unanimous answer’Ga naar voetnoot3. Only in the very deed can this selfhood of genius render itself objective. A true enthusiasm and optimism of the deed characterizes the period of ‘Sturm und Drang’, sharply distinguishing its basic tone from the preponderatingly pessimistic one of Rousseau, nothwithstanding all its dependence upon Rousseau's philosophy of sentiment. | |
[pagina 453]
| |
The irrationalist view of the individuality of genius. The irrationalist turn in the ideal of personality.This entire movement was still bound to Rousseau by the naturalistic view of the personality-ideal expressed in the watchword, ‘natural forming of life’. But for the rationalism of the time of the Enlightenment the ‘natural’ was identical with what was ‘conceived in terms of natural laws’. In contrast the ‘Sturm und Drang’ movement ran to the other extreme: it absolutizes the subjective individuality in nature: the genius must realize himself in the completely individual expression of his psychical drives. The true reality is sought in the completely irrational depths of subjective individuality and these depths of subjective reality are to be grasped not by the analysing understanding, but by feeling. This irrational philosophy of feeling, predominating especially in Hamann, the young Herder and Jacobi, and of which Goethe makes his Faust the mouth-piece in the utterance: ‘Gefühl ist alles’, is the true Humanistic counter-pole of the rationalistic line of thought characteristic of the ‘Enlightenment’. The philosophy of life of the ‘Sturm und Drang’ period finds its culminating point in the demand for subjective ethical freedom. This new Humanistic postulate of freedom is averse to all universal rational norms. Gelpcke characterizes it as follows: ‘The regained concept of freedom becomes a dogma. It is freedom against every rule, every authority, every compulsion of the wrong society. Consequently, it implies unconditional freedom of feeling from all dependence, just as the Enlightenment had preached the unconditional freedom of reason’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
Tension between the irrationalist conception of freedom and the science-ideal in its Leibnizian form in Herder. The antinomy is sought in ‘life’ itself. The Faust- and the Prometheus-motive.The Humanistic ideal of personality discloses itself here in an irrationalist type, still oriented to the aesthetic view of nature, but exhibiting all the more strongly its polarity with the ratio- | |
[pagina 454]
| |
nalistic science-ideal from which ‘Sturm und Drang’, despite its passionate protest against deterministic rationalism, never was able to liberate itself definitively. This is especially evident in Herder's philosophy of history, with its naturalistic concept of development derived from Leibniz. Antinomy is not shunned, but rather sought for in the very reality of life. ‘Faust’ and ‘Prometheus’ become the favourite problems of this period. Faust contends with nature, from which he wished to wrest her deepest secrets, in a boundless striving toward power and infinity. Prometheus is the stormer of heaven, who in Titanic pride brings fire from heaven to earth. Klopstock has given to his Prometheus-motive the following pregnant expression: ‘Forces of the other world are contained in the Idea of God, but man feels like a second Creator, able to reflect the Idea of the universe’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
The irrationalist Idea of humanity and the appreciation of individuality in history.The new ideal of humanity did not spring from mathematical thought, but from the irrational depths of feeling. It displays itself in a boundless reverence for all that man is, and, as such, possesses irrational creative individuality. It further displays itself in an appreciation of historical individuality in people (Volk), nation and state, usually strange to the time of the Enlightenment. The conception of ‘Sturm und Drang’ about individuality has indeed no longer anything in common with the atomistic individualism of the time of the Enlightenment. It is an irrationalist view that gains ground here, and that seeks everywhere after the irrational relations by which the individual is a part of the totality of an individual community. It is this very view which is characteristic of the philosophy of history of a Herder, who tries to understand the voice of history by way of empathy, by feeling himself into the spirit of historical individualities. Herder unhesitatingly accepts the polarity, the inner antinomy between this irrationalist view and the determinist conception of development, which he had taken over from Leibniz. Necessity of nature | |
[pagina 455]
| |
and creative freedom of the irreducible individuality come together in history and render impossible Kant's attempt at a separation of the two realms. In this philosophy of history, the science-ideal of the ‘Aufklärung’ still discloses its influence, insofar as historical development is thought of as subject to natural laws. In accordance with Leibniz' lex continui, development is here conceived of in increasingly complicated and more highly ordered series, as passing in a continuous transition from inorganic matter to organic life and human history, and as disclosing a steady progress in the evolution of culture. But this naturalistic cultural optimism is entirely pervaded and refined by the new humanity-ideal of the ‘Sturm und Drang’. The impulse toward a sympathetic understanding of every individuality in the cultural process protected this view of history from the rationalistic construction of world-history after the manner of Voltaire. | |
Fichte's third period and the influence of Jacobi. Transcendental philosophy in contrast with life-experience. The primacy of life and feeling.In what way then did the influence of the irrationalist philosophy of life, briefly sketched above, find expression in Fichte's third period, of which his writings: ‘Die Bestimmung des Menschen’, 1st ed., 1800, and his Sonnenklarer Bericht an das grössere Publikum über das eigentliche Wesen der neuesten Philosophie, are most strikingly charactistic? This influence discloses itself in the sharp cleavage, which Fichte here sets between theoretical knowledge and real life, identifying the latter with feeling, desire and actionGa naar voetnoot1, and placing the full accent of value upon life in opposition to philosophical speculation. In his Rückerinnrungen, Antworten, Fragen (Remembrances, Answers, Questions), an unpublished writing of the year 1799, Fichte observes: ‘Now the goal is life, and in no way speculation, the latter is only a means (an instrument) to form life, for it resides in an entirely other world, and what is to influence life, must itself have originated from life. It is only a means to know life’Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
[pagina 456]
| |
A little further on we read: ‘Life in its true essence is not-philosophizing; philosophizing in its true essence is not-life... There is here a complete antithesis, and a point of juncture is as surely impossible, as the conception of the X that rests at the foundation of the subject-object ego...’Ga naar voetnoot1. The opposition between his own philosophic standpoint and that of his opponents who accused him of atheism (Eberhard and others), is here formulated as follows: ‘The true seat of the conflict between my philosophy and the opposed doctrines, which are more or less aware of this situation, concerns the relation between (mere, objectively directed) knowledge and life (feeling, appetitive power and action). The opposed systems make knowledge the principle of life: they believe that through free, arbitrary thought they can originate some knowledge and concepts and implant them in man by means of reasoning and that thereby would be produced feelings, the appetitive power would be affected and thus finally human action determined. For them knowledge is consequently the higher, life is the lower and absolutely dependent on the former... Our philosophy, on the contrary, makes life, the system of feelings and appetitions the highest and allows to knowledge everywhere only the looking on’ (italics are mine)Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
[pagina 457]
| |
Hegel as opposed to the philosophy of life and feeling.In order to realize the polar distance which separates Fichte's philosophic thought in this period from Hegel's identity-philosophy, it is only necessary to compare these utterances as to the relation of the dialectical concept and the reality of life (seized immediately in feeling) with Hegel's following pronouncement in his Encyclopaedia: ‘It is wrong to suppose that the things which form the contents of our representations were first, and our subjective activity which through the earlier mentioned operation of abstracting and synthesizing of the common characteristics of the objects, produces the concepts of the same, would come only afterwards. The concept is rather the true first’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
Kant's sensory matter of experience is now the ‘true reality’ to Fichte.Kant's irrational ‘sensory matter of experience’, which in the ‘Critique of Pure Reason’ played only the negative rôle of a limit for the transcendental possibility of knowledge, acquired in Fichte's third period the positive meaning of ‘true reality’. Only the ‘material of experience’ accessible to immediate feeling, not yet ‘logically synthesized’ and deeply irrational, can claim to be reality. In the impressive conclusion of the second book of the writing Die Bestimmung des Menschen (The Vocation of Man), the ‘spirit’ says to the ‘ego’ that wished to come to knowledge of reality through the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’: ‘All theoretical knowledge is only image, and there is always something required in it which corresponds to the image. This demand cannot be satisfied by any theoretical knowledge; and a system of science is necessarily a system of mere images, without any reality, significance and aim... Now you seek after all something real which resides outside the mere image... and another reality than that which was destroyed just now, as I know likewise. However, it would be in vain, if you would try to create it through and from your knowledge and to | |
[pagina 458]
| |
embrace it with your science. If you have no other organ to grasp it, you shall never find it. However, you do possess such an organ. Vivify it only and warm it: and you shall come to complete rest. I leave you alone with yourself’Ga naar voetnoot1. In agreement with Jacobi, Fichte now seeks this other organ in belief, which he, together with this philosopher of feeling, views as the diametrical opposite of cognitive thought. Jacobi had taught that the ‘unconditional Being’ could not be demonstrated theoretically, but could only be felt immediately. And he had not restricted the truth-value of immediate feeling to the bounds of sense perception, but had proclaimed as its second basic form the certainty of supra-sensory belief. In like manner, Fichte, too, now teaches that the true reality is discovered only by belief, rooted in the immediate feeling of the drive to absolute, independent activityGa naar voetnoot2. Jacobi supposed his view to be based upon naïve experience when he identified the latter with the function of feeling. Fichte follows suit in teaching that naïve man, even without being aware of it, grasps all reality existing for him, only by faithful feeling: ‘We all are born in belief; who is blind, follows blindly the secret and irresistible drive; he who sees, follows seeing; and believes because he wants to believe’Ga naar voetnoot3. This faith is no longer the a-priori practical reasonable faith of Kant, that elevates abstract noumenal Ideas to a practical reality ‘in itself’. It is rather Jacobi's emotional faith, that this thinker set again, in the old nominalist manner, in opposition | |
[pagina 459]
| |
to the understanding in his famous expressilon: ‘Heathen with the head, Christian with the heart’Ga naar voetnoot1. It must, however, be borne in mind that Jacobi supposed he found true Christianity in the well-known postulates of the Humanistic ideal of personality: belief in the personality of God, in moral freedom and autonomy, and in the immortality of human personality, whereas Fichte, who identified the Deity with the ‘moral order of the universe’, abandoned the belief in a personal God. It was this that brought upon him the charge of atheïsm. The relationship which Fichte here accepts between ‘faith’ and reflective thinking also diverges diametrically from that which he accepts between the two in his Staatslehre of 1813. In the last mentioned work all progress in history is seen as a methodical victory of the understanding over faith ‘until the former has entirely destroyed the latter and has brought its content into the more noble form of clear insight’Ga naar voetnoot2. Yet a great mistake would be made, if the agreement between the philosophy of feeling and Fichte's standpoint in his third period were interpreted as a complete surrender to the former. Even Lask, who for the most part clearly indicates the points of difference, goes too far in imputing to Fichte a radical depreciation of the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’ in his third periodGa naar voetnoot3. He has overlooked that the same writing in which Fichte ascribes the discovery of true reality to vital feeling alone - allowing to philosophy only the ‘Zusehen’ (looking on) - concludes with a veritable eulogy of the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’: ‘In short: by the acceptance and universal propagation of the doctrine of science among those to whom it is appropriate, the whole of mankind shall be freed from blind chance and fate shall be destroyed for the same. All mankind becomes its own master under the control of its own concept; it makes henceforth itself with absolute | |
[pagina 460]
| |
liberty into everything, into which it can only want to make itself’Ga naar voetnoot1. Jacobi was never able to recognize the value of the ‘doctrine of science’. To Fichte, on the contrary, even in his closest approach to the philosophy of feeling, it remained the only way to conceive the full consequences of the freedom-motive, just as, even at this time, he never abandoned the transcendental moralistic standpoint and never fell into the aestheticism of the philosophy of life and feelingGa naar voetnoot2. | |
Recognition of the individual value of the empirical as such. Fichte's estimation of individuality contrasted with that of Kant. Individualizing of the categorical imperative.In this period the recognition of the value of ‘empirical’ individuality goes hand in hand with the recognition of ‘feeling’ as an immediate source of knowledge of reality. In his frequently cited writing Lask has given a keen analysis of the fundamental difference between Kant's transcendental-logical concept of ‘empirical’ individuality and the conception developed by Fichte in his third period concerning the epistemological individual value of the ‘empirical’ as such. Kant was not able to ascribe any value to empirical individuality as such, and could qualify it only as contingent in contrast with the norms of reason which alone have value. For Fichte, on the contrary, empirical individuality has now acquired an inner value as being rooted in the individuality of the moral ego itself. Even in Fichte's System der Sittenlehre (System of Ethics) of 1798 this recognition of the value of individuality discloses itself in his supplement to the formal principle of Ethics. Kant's ‘universally valid’ categorical imperative is in- | |
[pagina 461]
| |
dividualized. It comes now to read as follows: ‘Act in conformity with your individual destination, and your individual situation’Ga naar voetnoot1. The individuality of the empirical world, incomprehensible in a theoretical way, acquires practical significance for the personality, insofar as the material of our individual duty discloses itself in itGa naar voetnoot2. In each individual act of perceiving and knowing is concealed a ‘practical’ kernel of feeling, in spite of its theoretical functionGa naar voetnoot3. In this connection, too, the estimation of individuality is fastened to the immediate evidence of feeling: ‘whether I doubt or am sure, it does not originate from argumentation... but from immediate feeling... this feeling never deceives’Ga naar voetnoot4. In the Wissenschaftslehre of 1801 the principle of individuation (principium individuationis) is explicitly sought in feeling as the concentration-point of knowledge (Konzentrationspunkt des Wissens)Ga naar voetnoot5. | |
No radical irrationalism in Fichte's third period.Thanks to the influence of the transcendental critical line of thought, which never completely disappeared from the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’, there never was, in the case of Fichte himself, a complete victory of an irrationalist philosophy of feeling. The moralistic law of reason is not abrogated, even where, in his third period, the recognition of the value of what is individually experienced in feeling makes itself increasingly operative in his moralistic and activistic ideal of personality. Fichte seeks only to individualize its content within the cadre of its universally valid form. | |
[pagina 462]
| |
§ 2 - Aesthetic irrationalism in the humanistic ideal of personality. The ideal of the ‘beautiful soul’. Elaboration of the irrationalist freedom-motive in the modern philosophy of life and its polar tension with the science-idealSo much the stronger does the irrationalist turn in the Humanistic ideal of personality assert itself in the feeling-philosophy of ‘Sturm und Drang’ and in early Romanticism. From the outset, this tendency proceeds in an aesthetic direction. Here, Kant's ‘Critique of Aesthetic Judgment’, with its orientation of the aesthetic judgment to free feeling and with its recognition of the absolute individual value of the genius, offered an immediate point of contact. | |
Schiller and Kant's ‘Critique of Aesthetic Judgment’. Aesthetic idealism. The influence of Shaftesbury.Schiller transformed this theory into an aesthetic idealism, in which the aesthetic aspect of meaning is elevated to the rank of the deepest root of reality. Behind Kant's influence on this point, there was here at work Shaftesbury's aesthetic ethics of virtuosity. As CassirerGa naar voetnoot1 has shown, Shaftesbury's aesthetics had a decisive significance for Kant's own aesthetic views. Even in Shaftesbury (1671-1713), the Humanistic ideal of personality, in an irrationalist transformation of the Greek ideal of ϰαλοϰάγαϑον, was converted into the principle of aesthetic morality of the genius, turning against every supra-individual norm and law. True morality does not consist in the rule of general maxims, nor in the subjection of subjectivity to a universal norm, but in a harmonious, aesthetic self-realization of the total individuality. The highest disclosure of the sovereign personality in the moral realm is virtuosity, which allows no single power and instinctive tendency in the individual talent to languish, but brings them all into aesthetic harmony by means of a perfect practice of life, and thereby realizes the happiness of the individual as well as the welfare of the entire society. In the nature of the case, this ethics of virtuosity cannot find the source of moral knowledge in the rational functions directed to general laws, but only in the subjective depths of individual feeling. | |
[pagina 463]
| |
Accordingly, morality was brought under a subjective and aesthetic basic denominator. The morally good was regarded as the beautiful in the world of practical volition and action: according to Shaftesbury, the good, like the beautiful, consists in a harmonious unity of the manifold, in a complete unfolding of that which slumbers in the individual nature as subjective talent. It is, just like the beautiful, the object of an original approbation, rooted in the deepest being of man: thus ‘taste’ becomes the basic faculty for ethics as well as for aesthetics. This aesthetic philosophy of feeling has acquired a profound influence, even though Hutcheson and the Scottish school replaced the absolutism of individuality in Shaftesbury by the absolutism of law, characteristic of the rationalistic types of the Humanistic cosmonomic Idea. As we saw before, the turn that Rousseau gave to the Humanistic freedom-motive, in the emancipation of personality from the grip of the science-ideal, rests essentially on a mobilizing of the undepraved natural feeling against the sober analysing understanding of the Enlightenment-period. With the Dutch philosopher, Franz Hemsterhuys, and the philosophers of life of the ‘Sturm und Drang’ this philosophy of feeling recaptures its original, irrationalist character, disclosing itself in an absolutizing of the aesthetic individuality. | |
The ideal of ‘the beautiful soul’.In Schiller's aesthetic Humanism, the irrationalist and aesthetic conception of the ideal of personality embodies itself, though within the formal limits of transcendental idealism, in the Idea of the ‘beautiful soul’. The philosophical basic-denominator of reality is shifted to the aesthetic aspect of meaning viewed exclusively from its individual subjective side. Beauty is, according to Schiller's definition, ‘freedom in appearance (phenomenon)’Ga naar voetnoot1. In the aesthetic play-drive (‘Spieltrieb’), the fulness of human personality, and therein of the cosmos, becomes evident. Man is really man only where he is playing, where the conflict between sensuous nature and rational moral freedom in him is silent. Kant's rigorist morality holds only for the man who has not yet matured to full harmony, in whose innermost being the moral impulse must still wage war with sensuous nature. In the ‘beautiful soul’, however, | |
[pagina 464]
| |
there is realized the harmony that no longer knows this combat, for its nature is so ennobled, that it does good out of natural impulse. Only by aesthetic education does a man acquire this refinement. In this way alone is the discord between sensuous and super-sensuous functions in human nature reconciled. Windelband has keenly fathomed the attempt at a solution of all antinomies between the ideals of science and personality undertaken by this aesthetic Humanism, in which the second German Renaissance attains its point of culmination. As to this point he remarks: ‘This second Renaissance of the Germans is not only the completion of the former, which had been broken off in the midst, but it contains also the first consciousness of the basic drive which inspired the whole European Renaissance. Not before this aesthetic Humanism had there been the awareness of the deepest meaning of all contrasts in whose reconcilation modern culture finds its task. The two sides of the human being, whose harmonical reconcilation is the very content of culture; have assumed manifold proportions in the historical movement. In antique culture the sensuous prevails, in Christian culture the supra-sensuous man. From the very outset it was the tendency of modern culture to find the full reconciliation of these two developments. The sensuous nature of man rules his scientific knowledge, the supra-sensuous determines his ethical consciousness and the faith fastened to the latter. It is the continuous striving of modern thought to find the synthesis of this “twofold truth”. However, the sensuous supra-sensuous nature of man discloses itself as complete totality only in its aesthetical function. Therefore, the whole Renaissance was in the first place artistically moved...! This was the very greatness of the epoch, that at the same time this synthesis of the sensuous and the supra-sensuous man was living in the modern Greek, in Goethe. And it is the immortal merit of Schiller that he has understood this moment in its deepest signification and that he has formulated it according to all its directions. He is truly the prophet of the self-consciousness of modern culture’Ga naar voetnoot1. Windelband supposes, that he can identify the antinomy between sensuous nature and the supra-sensuous moral consciousness in the Humanistic freedom-idealism with the tension between Greek and Christian culture. This testifies to a fun- | |
[pagina 465]
| |
damental lack of insight into the fact that the Humanistic ideal of personality in its moralistic conception is not essentially Christian, but rather a secularization of the Christian Idea of freedom implying an apostasy from the latter. | |
The ‘morality of genius’ in early Romanticism.In Schiller's more mature period, aesthetic irrationalism was still held within the limits of transcendental idealism. In the ‘morality of genius’ of early Romanticism, however, where the morality of the ‘beautiful soul’ becomes religion, this irrationalism discloses itself in its radical senseGa naar voetnoot1. By way of Schelling, it would dig itself a wide channel in the most recent philosophy of life, with its fundamental depreciation of the science-ideal and its absolutizing of ‘creative evolution’. | |
The tension of the ideals of science and personality in Nietzsche's development. Biologizing of the science-ideal (Darwin).The Humanistic ideal of personality in its irrationalist turn was confronted with a new development of the natural science-ideal which, since the second half of the nineteenth century under the mighty influence of Darwin's evolution-theory, pervaded the new ‘historical mode of thought’. As we shall presently show, this new ‘historical mode of thinking’ originated in the irrationalistic turn of the Humanistic freedom-idealism. This dialectical struggle between the two basic factors of the Humanistic transcendental ground-Idea in their new conception discloses itself in a truly impressive manner in the dialectical development of Nietzsche, whose final phase, as we observed in an earlier context, is, the announcement of the beginning of the religious uprooting of modern thought as a result of a dialectical self-destruction of the Humanistic ground-motive in a radical Historicism. We have only to compare Nietzsche's first romantic-aesthetic period, influenced strongly by Schopenhauer and Richard Wagner, with the second positivistic phase beginning in 1878, | |
[pagina 466]
| |
in which the biological ideal of science gains the upper-hand, and the last period of the culture-philosophy of the ‘Superman’, beginning in 1883. In this last period, the science-ideal has been entirely depreciated. Henceforth, science is viewed as a merely biological means in the struggle for existence, without any proper truth-value. Bergson and other modern philosophers of life took over this pragmatist and biological conception of the theoretical picture of the world, created by scientific thought. It would be false to suppose that the irrationalist philosophy of life preached chaos. On the contrary, it does not intend to abandon order. But, as the rationalist types of Humanist philosophy make the concept of the subject a function of the concept of the law in a special modal sense, and thus dissolve the former into the latter, so, in a reverse manner, the irrationalist types reduce the ‘true’ order to a function of individual subjectivity. | |
The relationship of αὐτός and νόμος in the irrationalist ideal of personality. Dialectical character of the philosophy of life. Modern dialectical phenomenology.In Kant's formulation of the Humanistic ideal of personality, the true αὐτός discovers itself only in the νόμος; in the irrationalist conception of autonomy the νόμος (nomos) is rather a reflex of the absolutely individual αὐτός. Rationalism and irrationalism in their modern sense are merely polar contrasts in the basic structure of the Humanistic cosmonomic Idea. The tension, the inner antinomy that originates for the irrationalist types between absolutized subjective individuality and law, led Hamann and early romanticism to a dialectical conception of reality which ascribed the character of absolute reality to logical contradiction. In the modern dialectical phenomenology, issuing from Dilthey's irrationalist historical philosophy of life, ‘dialectical thinking’ has this same irrationalist character; it is sharply to be distinguished from Husserl's rationalist phenomenologyGa naar voetnoot1. In this dialectical trait of irrationalism, we can once again | |
[pagina 467]
| |
find the proof of the thesis that in the last analysis, even the irrationalist types of Humanist philosophy are rooted in an absolutizing of the theoretical attitude of thought. An antinomy is always the product of the failure of theoretical thought to recognize its boundaries. In pre-theoretical naïve experience theoretical antinomies are out of the question. The sanctioning of a theoretical antinomy bears the stamp of a subjective attitude of thought directed against the cosmic order and the basic logical laws functioning in the latter. This attitude of thought is indubitably a component part of sinful reality, but only insofar as its anti-normative meaning is determined by the cosmic order and by the logical norms within this order, against which it turns itself in revolt. Sanctioning antinomy in the identification of dialectical thought with irrational reality, signifies a meaningless negation of the law-side of reality founded in the cosmic order. This negation is meaningless, because subjectivity without an order that defines it can have no existence and meaning. | |
The types of the irrationalist cosmonomic Idea of Humanistic thought.As rationalism in the Humanist philosophy is shaded into various mutually antagonistic types of cosmonomic Ideas, so is irrationalism. In principle we can think of as many types of irrationalism as there are non-logical aspects of temporal reality. | |
§ 3 - The genesis of a new concept of science from the humanistic ideal of personality in its irrationalist types. Fichte's fourth periodThe Humanistic ideal of personality, having become aware of its own deepest tendencies, must in the long run transfer its tension with the mechanistic science-ideal to the realm of special scientific thought. The continuity-postulate of the Humanistic freedom-motive could not finally accept the Kantian identification of scientific thought with that of mathematical natural-science. It could not finally abandon in this way its claims to the knowledge of temporal reality. Humanistic philosophy had in its pre-Kantian rationalist types proclaimed the supremacy of the mathematical science-ideal over the normative aspects of temporal reality. | |
[pagina 468]
| |
Kant brought, as we saw, the antinomy between the ideals of science and personality to a pregnant formulation, and established between the two the actio finium regundorum. Fichte had begun to deprive the mechanical science-ideal of its independence with respect to the ideal of personality and to deduce the former from the latter. The moment must come in which this carrying through of the primacy of the personality-ideal would make itself felt in special scientific thought and contend the exclusive dominion of the mathematical-physical conception of science. The stimulus to this development could only issue from the irrationalist currents which had absolutized the subjective side of the normative aspects of human existence in its complete individuality under this or that basic denominator, and had resolved the rationalist Idea of the lex into an irrationalist Idea of the subject. Where else but in the individual subjectivity could the freedom-motive of the irrationalist Humanistic ideal of personality have made its dominion over ‘empirical’ reality felt? If subjective individuality is no longer proclaimed with Kant as a merely negative logical limit of mathematical causal knowledge, but rather as empirical reality ϰαἰ ἐξοχήν, the whole view of human experience must be altered in principle. Natural-scientific thought, suited only for the discovery of universally valid laws, could then no longer raise the pretension of providing us with genuine knowledge of the whole field of empirical reality. | |
Orientation of a new science-ideal to the science of history.From the outset we see the irrationalist types in Humanistic philosophy concentrating their attention upon the science of history, which by the coryphaei of the Enlightenment period was denatured to a crypto-natural science with strong ethicizing tendencies (the ideal of the necessary progress of mankind through the illumination of thought!). It must immediately become evident that the method of natural science cannot grasp the proper ‘Gegenstand’ of historical research, as soon as the ban of the mathematical science-ideal was broken by the antagonistic pretensions of an irrationalistically conceived ideal of personality. Kant's transcendental critique of teleological judgment had still only cleared the way for a philosophy of history, oriented, to a certain extent at | |
[pagina 469]
| |
least, to the personality-ideal, still conceived of in essentially rationalist terms. His teleological view of historical development, as explained in his treatise On Eternal Peace (Vom ewigen Frieden) did not lay claim to a scientific character. In order to wrest special scientific historical thought from the supremacy of the rationalistic science-ideal, there was needed first and foremost a fundamentally different evaluation of subjective individuality. It was originally an aesthetic irrationalism that even in Herder's Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784-1791) - although here still checked by Leibniz' rationalist Idea of development - cleared the way for an irrationalist method of cultivating the science of history: an empathetic and sympathetic treatment of the historical contexts in their incomparable individuality. Presently, Schelling's organological idealism was to provide the philosophical equipment for the view of history held by the Historical school, with its doctrine of the originally unconscious growth of culture from the historical ‘Volksgeist’ in the individual nationalities. The spirit of restoration which acquired the upper hand after the liquidation of the French revolution and the fall of Napoleon, naturally favoured the rise of the historical mode of thought. The apriori constructions of state and society by the Humanistic school of natural law were replaced by the historical insight that state, society, law and culture in general cannot be ‘created’ from mathematical thought after a pattern valid for all times and for every people, but are rather a result of a long historical evolution of a people whose ‘spirit’ has an irreducible individuality. The rise of the science of sociology in the early part of the nineteenth century was also an important factor in the development of a new historical mode of thought; this sociology, however, intended to perform a synthesis between the latter and the natural scientific pattern of thought, which synthesis presently was to lead to an invasion of Darwinist evolutionism in historical science. | |
Fichte in his fourth period and the South-West-German school of Neo-Kantianism.In the present connection, however, we will restrict ourselves to an inquiry after the contribution given by Fichte, in his | |
[pagina 470]
| |
fourth metaphysical period, to the methodology of historical thought. From this context, a clear light falls over the epistemology of historical thought, propagated in recent times by the South-West-German school of the Neo-Kantians, especially by its two leading figures, Rickert and Max Weber. Lask's researches in particular have shown that it was essentially the fundamental change in the valuation of individuality which brought Fichte in his fourth period to a speculative metaphysics completely different from the identity-philosophy which we find in the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’ of 1794. Fichte's later development is indeed to be seen in full connection with the rather general opposition arising at this time against the abstract Kantian criticism, brought to a head in the opposition between form and matter, and hostile to the true valuation of individuality. The so-called ‘critical’ method had concentrated all value in the universally valid forms of reason and had depreciated the individual, as the transcendental irrational, as ‘only empirical’, as the merely contingent instance of formal conformity to the law of reason. The irrationalistically orientated metaphysical idealists of this period, who had all passed under Kant's influence, now supposed they had to reject the entire critical method. To be sure, Kant, in his Critique of Judgment, had raised the problem of specification, but here too, only within the framework of the form-matter schema. Only in Aesthetics was he in a position to appreciate subjective individuality as such. The irrationalistically conceived freedom-motive demanded a new speculative method for the knowledge of individuality, and eventually it was under the inspiration of problems of the philosophy of culture that this motive began its contest against the old rationalist science-ideal. | |
Hegel's supposed ‘rationalism’.The new metaphysics of the absolute Being, as totality of individuality, is nothing but a metaphysics of the irrationalist ideal of personality. The later formal rationalizing of this irrationalism in Hegel's so-called ‘pan-logism’ is only a typical specimen of the inner polarity of the transcendental Humanistic ground-Idea; but it never warrants the neglect of the fact that this apparent rationalism is the very antipode of the rationalism after | |
[pagina 471]
| |
the pattern of the classical Humanistic science-ideal, oriented to mathematics and natural science. Schelling became the recognized leader in the controversy against formalistic transcendental idealism. The conception of knowledge in terms of the abstract Kantian form-matter schema - in which, as we saw previously, all antinomies between the ideals of science and personality were crowded together - was to be abrogated. Philosophy was to be understood as ‘the absolute knowledge of the absolute’. Here an association was made with the old speculative motive of an intuitive divine understanding, to which there were also allusions in Kant's Kritik der Urteilskraft. But it was now liberated from the mathematical ideal of science. It was not the Idea of the uno intuito perfected mathematical analysis (Leibniz) that inspired the new ‘idealism of the spirit’. | |
‘Intellectual intuition’ in Schelling.In contrast to the dualistically separated sources of knowledge in the Kantian critique of knowledge, Schelling posits the ‘intellectual intuition’ in which the absolute totality of meaning is comprehended by a single all-embracing glance. Krause elevates the knowledge of the arch-essential (das ur-wesentliche), the intuition of essence, above the relative knowledge from concepts. Troxler, with explicit appeal to Jacobi, sets the arch-consciousness or immediate knowledge in opposition to reflecting and discursive thought, and Solger contests the dualism of the universal and particular. In his Lectures on the Method of Academic Study, delivered in 1802 at the university of Jena, Schelling appealed to a method of genius for scientific insightGa naar voetnoot1 and in so doing he simply gave expression to the whole spirit of this time, which was deeply inspired by the irrationalist ideal of personality. Everywhere it is the value of absolute individuality that one hoped to grasp | |
[pagina 472]
| |
by a speculative metaphysical method of intellectual intuition immediately grasping the absolute. In opposition to the irrationalism of feeling on the part of ‘Sturm und Drang’, all attention is now directed to the individual disclosure of the ‘Spirit’, of the ‘Idea’. | |
Hegel's new dialectical logic and its historical orientation.In his younger days, Hegel himself had lived in the sphere of the irrationalist philosophy of feeling. In his mature period, he rationalized the irrationalist thought of Romanticism by his new dialectical logic, which in its kernel is nothing but an antirationalist, universalistic logic of historical development. Lask correctly observes that the very structure of the individual totality, as exhibited for example in the transpersonalistic-universalistic conception of the state as a ‘moral organism’, becomes the pattern for Hegel's conception of the structure of the logical concept. The break with the logic of the naturalistic ideal of science - a logic which had led to an atomistic individualism in the field of philosophy of culture - was indeed inescapable after the victory of the irrationalist ideal of personality. Hegel's positive work was the creation of a new speculative metaphysical logic of individuality, by which he sought simply to replace the natural scientific logic of the Humanistic ideal of science, along the entire line of human knowledge. With Hegel the irrationalist and idealist conception of the ideal of personality creates its own metaphysical logic. Thereby it sets itself sharply in opposition to critical idealism, which in spite of its ascription of the primacy to the ideal of personality, nevertheless, in its method of forming concepts had remained entirely oriented to the logic of the naturalistic science-ideal. Fichte's ‘metaphysics of spirit’, which speedily gained the upper-hand in his thought after the brief period of his approach toward the philosophy of life, also originated essentially from the irrationalistic and universalistic conception of the freedom-motive with its orientation to problems of the philosophy of culture. In contrast with the problem of the universally-valid transcendental ego of the first sketches of the ‘doctrine of science’, there emerged even in his System der Sittenlehre (1798) the question of the individual ego. This compelled him to proceed beyond the immanent transcendental analysis of consciousness and | |
[pagina 473]
| |
to raise the question as to the metaphysical foundations in being for the spiritual lifeGa naar voetnoot1. To the essence of self-consciousness of one's own ego belongs, as Fichte clearly realizes, the consciousness of the other ego, the Thou. Concrete freedom and autonomous determination of the will arise only in the immediate connection of the individual ego with other ‘spiritual beings’. It is no longer satisfactory to deduce my knowledge of other egos, as a necessary activity of consciousness, from the transcendental self-consciousness. The other egos, the plurality of spiritual beings outside myself, have an altogether other mode of being with respect to myself than the material external world (‘nature’). | |
The problem of the ‘Realität der Geisterwelt’ (reality of the world of spirits).The problem of the reality of the ‘Geisterwelt’ (world of spirits) emerges and it arises from the moral foundation of the ego itself, from the duty to recognize every free individual as an independent moral ‘end in himself’. The ego must not only think or intuit the other egos in itself (as if they were natural things), but it stands also in a real spiritual contact, in a living spiritual exchange with them. Consequently, the syntheses performed by the transcendental ego of the critical doctrine of science did not exhaust the development of the syntheses of the system of reason. The latter urgently demand a conclusion in a metaphysical ‘synthesis of the real world of spirits’ (Heimsoeth). In the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’ of 1801 this highest metaphysical synthesis is viewed as a synthesis of the absolute Being with infinite freedom. The individual ego is one of the many concentration-points of the ‘Absolute Spirit’, of the Origin of the cosmos. It has the form of existence (‘Dasein’) from the absolute Being, but definite, concrete, individual being from the interaction of its freedom with the totality of the spiritual worldGa naar voetnoot2. Consequently, Fichte seeks the original, essential reality of all finite individual selves in a transpersonally conceived life of reason. The individual egos are not substances, but individual differentiations and ‘forms of manifestation’ of the one infinite | |
[pagina 474]
| |
life of reason; the ‘bond of union’ in the world of spirits is not a joining afterwards of isolated ego-monads; it is much rather the fundamental communion of all individual egos as appearance of the infinite Origin, from which the free spiritual beings, with all their spiritual interactions, originate by a metaphysical actus individuationis in which time itself acquires individual points of concentrationGa naar voetnoot1. Thus, even in Fichte's fourth period, the ideal of personality acquires that trans-personalist turn which was to find its consummation in Hegel's identity-philosophy of the absolute self-developing Idea. | |
Trans-personalist turn in the ideal of personality. The new conception of the ‘ordo ordinans’ in Fichte's pantheistic metaphysics.The being of the ‘Spirit’ is a transpersonal being of freedom, which, in the totality of individual spiritual life, realizes its infinite actual freedom, still preceding all thought. The ‘moral order of the world’, as the infinite active ordo ordinans, or the ‘infinite will’, now becomes the trans-personal bond of union for all finite spirits in their individual moral destination. It has become the true antipode, irrationalist in its deepest root, of Kant's abstract ‘universally valid categorical imperative.’ The ethical individuality of the ego, in Fichte's irrationalist conception of it, leads through itself to a trans-personal community of free spirits. Only from this totality of the community may | |
[pagina 475]
| |
spiritual individuality be understood. The concept of ‘material freedom’ consequently gains in Fichte a trans-personal character which, from the start, was tuned to the grasping of the objective cultural coherences, in which the individuals are interwovenGa naar voetnoot1. Fichte's philosophy of history is only to be understood in the framework of this transpersonalist and, at least in its root, irrationalist metaphysics of the spirit. Meanwhile, this metaphysics finds its conclusion only in a final hypostasis; the absolute Being, raised above all becoming and change, of the impersonal, because actually infinite Divinity. This absolute Being is eternally transcendent to all reflection, to all knowledge, and it is not an external ‘Ding an sich’, but the inner real ground of the possibility of rational freedom with all its finite manifestations. As such, however, it is at the same time the absolutely irrational, the completely incomprehensible. All life is only manifestation, image or schema of God, the finite ‘existence’ (Dasein), the finite form of manifestation of the absolute Being. But only in the moral freedom of human personality does the appearance of this absolute Being have immediate ‘Dasein’ (existence). ‘Nature’ in the sense of the naturalistic science-ideal is only the appearance of the reasonable ethical appearance of God. This latter discloses itself in the trans-personal individual life of the free ethical world of spirits. Nature continues to lack independent meaning with reference to the ethical aspects of the cosmos. Not in ‘nature’, but in ethical activity only does God reveal himself in the ‘appearance’. The earlier rationalist deification of the moral law is now replaced by an entirely irrationalist idea of God. God has become the absolute hypostasis of the creative, subjective ethical stream of life, which is the trans-personal bond and totality of the individual free subjects. | |
[pagina 476]
| |
Fichte's basic denominator for the aspects of meaning becomes historical in character. Fichte's philosophy of history.Yet - and this is of the highest importance in this new metaphysics of spirit - the moral basic denominator, to which Fichte apparently still reduces all aspects of temporal reality and which finds its final hypostasis in the irrationalist Idea of God, is, nevertheless, under the influence of the irrationalist ideal of personality, itself transformed into an historical basic denominator. Heimsoeth correctly observes: ‘For the first time in the history of philosophy, the specific reality of historical existence is not only conceived of as an original reality of metaphysical rank, but it is even interpreted as the final mode of being of finite existence as such... The modern pathos of the “book of nature” is replaced by the metaphysical-religious conception of history as the proper mode of appearance of the Absolute or the divine Spirit. The world presents itself to Fichte as an infinite active chain of “challenges”, of freedom-evoking and spirit-cultivating interaction of self-acting life-centres, in creative freedom producing new and new faces as it were from nothing’Ga naar voetnoot1. The absolute ethical Idea, the absolute Being, assumes a purely historical mode of appearance in its manifestation in the ‘spiritual life’ of the temporal human community. It schematizes itself in the infinite movement of the development of history, in which the Deity, in creative irrational fashion, continually assumes new spiritual forms of manifestation. The theme of history for Fichte, just as for Kant, is that of striving upwards to freedom. But in Fichte's fourth period, the higher ethos of the spiritual life is no longer, as in Kant, conceived rationalistically in the formalistic Idea of autonomy, in which the autos only comes to itself in the nomos, i.e. the formal categorical impera- | |
[pagina 477]
| |
tive. It is rather conceived in the irrationalist sense of the ‘creative’ historical process, in which the one absolute metaphysical Idea, through the concentration-points of the great leading personalities, realizes itself in the diverse forms of cultural Ideas: in the Ideas of art, state, science and religion. The inner value of the latter corresponds to their precedenceGa naar voetnoot1. In this period, Fichte is deeply convinced of the irrationality of the absolute Idea in its inexhaustible creative fulness of lifeGa naar voetnoot2. Only in the spiritual originality of great individuals, of creative geniuses, does the divine image immediately break through into appearance. History, as an immediate manifestation of the ethical Idea, is essentially made by great personalities. So Fichte himself expresses it: ‘All that is great and good, upon which our present existence is based, from which it starts, and which is the only supposition under which it can display its essence in the manner it does display it, has only been realized by the fact that noble and vigorous men have sacrificed all enjoyment of life for the sake of Ideas; and we ourselves with all that we are, are the result of the sacrifices of all previous generations, and especially of their most worthy fellow-members’Ga naar voetnoot3. ‘The original divine | |
[pagina 478]
| |
Idea of a definite standpoint in time is for the greater part not to be indicated before the (elected) man comes, inspired by God, and executes it... The original and pure divine Idea is in general... creative for the world of appearance, originating that which is new, unheard of and never had existed before.’ ‘From time immemorial it was a law of the super-sensory world that it only in few elected men... originally broke forth in visions: the great majority of the rest should only be cultivated by mediation of these few...’ ‘In the world of spirits the nobility of everything becomes greater according to its rareness... in extremely few (personalities) the Deity expresses itself immediately’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
Natural individuality must be annihilated in the historical process by the individuality of the spirit.The value of the individuality of genius, which Fichte sets here so emphatically in the foreground, is not that of the merely sensuous individuality of nature. Just as ‘nature’ as such possesses for Fichte no meaning of its own, so also must the individuality of nature (natural individuality) be annihilated for the sake of the disclosure of the absolute Idea. In a clear manner Fichte says that his ‘unconditional rejection of all individuality’ exclusively relates to the ‘personal sensory existence of the individual’, but that, on the contrary, his philosophy postulates that ‘in each particular individual in which it comes to life, the one eternal Idea absolutely exhibits itself in a new figure which never existed before; and this quite independent of the sensory nature, through itself and its own legislation, consequently by no means determined through the sensory individuality, but rather annihilating the latter and purely from itself determining the ideal individuality, or, as it is called more exactly, the originality’Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
Individuality and Society.As this ‘spiritual’ (historical) individuality is further thought | |
[pagina 479]
| |
of only as a point of concentration, in which the absolute Idea makes itself concrete in the historical supra-personal stream of life, there is automatically a break with the atomistic natural-scientific view of history. According to Fichte, individuality can only be understood from the individual communities, in which alone it has temporal existence. Even in his Reden an die deutsche Nation (1808), Fichte has made a serious attempt to conceive the individuality of a nation as an historical totality. The remarkable feature of this whole metaphysical conception, typical at the same time of its irrationalist root, is the nominalistic view, which denies both the reality of abstract general concepts (universalia) and the possibility of a derivation of subjectivity from a law. Fichte's absolute transcendent Idea is not a universal, but a totality. He rejects unconditionally every hypostatization of general concepts in the sense of Platonic ideas. In my opinion, it is also entirely incorrect to characterize Fichte's metaphysics as monistic Eleaticism, as Lask doesGa naar voetnoot1, The static Eleatic conception of ‘absolute being’ has nothing in common with Fichte's view of the absolute Idea as a totality of being, which unfolds itself in the historical process. The Eleatic being, as I have shown in the first volume of my trilogy Reformation and Scholasticism in Philosophy, is not to be understood apart from the religious form-motive of Greek thought. It is the indivisible, supra-sensory and divine form of being, as such, which can be intuited only in ‘theoria’, and which cannot have any relation to the ‘matter-principle’, the principle of becoming and declining. This ‘form of being’ is thought of as a purely geometrical one, corresponding to the immaterial shape of the sphere, which in Greek philosophy was viewed as the most perfect. Fichte's ‘divine Being’, on the contrary, although in itself supra-historical, has an essential relation to the historical process. It is the divine origin of all activity and cultural individuality, and is thus by no means to be characterized as a static ‘universal’. | |
Abandonment of the Critical form-matter schema.In Fichte's metaphysical conception of the Idea (as closed totality of its individual disclosures in historical development), the Critical form-matter schema is in principle broken through | |
[pagina 480]
| |
and abandoned. Within the framework of the latter schema, the totality of individual determinations could only be an Idea in the sense of a limiting-concept, by which transcendental thought is driven forward without being able to realize its demand because of its limitations in comprehending the empirical material of experience. The recognition of these limitations is here the point of departure. Fichte's irrationalistic metaphysics, on the contrary, follows the reverse course from the absolute totality as ‘absolute Being’. The ‘Idea’ is not thought of here as an eternal task for bridging over the cleavage between the form and matter of our knowledge, but rather as a metaphysical totality of all individuality. In proceeding from the absolute totality in this metaphysical sense, there is a constant threat of an apriori construction of historical development. Such a construction abandons the temporal material of experience, which, as merely empirical, as only simple phenomenon, is reasoned away in Fichte's metaphysics of history. To this metaphysical passion for apriori construction, Fichte fell victim in his first work on the philosophy of history, the Principial Traits of the Present Era (‘Grundzüge des gegenwärtigen Zeitalters’, 1804-'05). Here he observes: ‘if the philosopher has the task to deduce the phenomena, possible in experience, from the unity of his supposed Idea, then it is evident, that for the fulfilment of this task he does not at all need experience; and that he, merely as a philosopher, and strictly paying attention to his limitations, can do his work without allowing for any experience, and simply apriori, as it is called with the technical term, and that - in relation to our subject - he must be able to describe apriori the whole of time and all possible periods of it’Ga naar voetnoot1. Thus the Idea of an historical world-plan is construed apriori. Fichte defines it in a teleological sense: ‘the aim of the earthly | |
[pagina 481]
| |
life of mankind is this, that the latter should arrange all its relations within the same with liberty according to reason’Ga naar voetnoot1. ‘This world-plan is the Idea of the unity of the whole of human earthly life’Ga naar voetnoot2. Out of this apriori Idea Fichte deduces, once again apriori, his five chief periods of world-history. It is not the individual, but rather the ‘human race’ as a whole that functions as the subject of the latter. In this entire philosophical conception, there appears to be no point of contact for a methodological concept of history, as a condition for the cultivation of the science of history. The empirical science of history appears rather to be handed over to the ‘Chronikmaker’ (annalist), whereas the systematics of history is reserved entirely for the apriori metaphysics of history as ‘Vernunftwissenschaft’ (science of reason). Lask, however, has pointed out, that in the Grundzüge another motive in the philosophy of history announces itself alongside of this metaphysical one. The two motives may not entirely be brought into agreement. The latter is to be explained in terms of the continued operation of Critical-transcendental motives even in Fichte's last period. This second motive may be characterized as follows: our thinker by no means made the task of the philosophy of history to consist entirely in the construction of the world-plan, but he sets also the requirement that it should make a thorough logical analysis of the general conditions of ‘empirical existence’, as the material of historical construction. | |
Fichte's logic of historical thought.In this requirement of a ‘logic of the historical mode of enquiry’, not to be found in Kant, the irrational character of the historical material of experience is placed in the foreground. It is especially the important ninth lecture of the Grundzüge, in which Fichte set himself the task of a ‘transcendental logical’ delimitation of the concept of the historical field of investigation, | |
[pagina 482]
| |
and describes this task explicitly as a philosophical one. It is not the task of the historian to consider empirical existence and its conditions as such. Both belong to his pre-suppositions: ‘The question which are these conditions of empirical existence - what is to be pre-supposed for the mere possibility of a history as such, and what in the first place must be (present), before history can merely make a beginning - belongs to the competence of the philosopher, who has to guarantee to the historian his basis and foundation’Ga naar voetnoot1. With ‘timeless Being’ or ‘divine life’ plunging into earthly existence, or into the ‘flowing of life’ in time, infinity and irrationality are joined for knowledge. Physics is the science that investigates empirically the constant objective and periodically recurrent features of temporal existence, i.e. ‘nature’. Investigation directed toward the contents of the flowing time-series is called the science of history: ‘Its “Gegenstand” is the always inconceivable development of knowledge concerning the incomprehensible’Ga naar voetnoot2. While the historian accepts his ‘facts’ (facta) simply as such, the task of the philosopher of history, who sees through their logical structure, is ‘to comprehend them in their incomprehensibility’ and to render intelligible the appearance of their ‘contingency’ out of their character which is incomprehensible to the understanding. It is, consequently, the task of philosophy to indicate the boundary between speculation and experience in the study of history. At this point, the influence of Criticism on Fichte's view of history exhibits itself very clearly, where he opposes every attempt to deduce the historical facts themselves from the infinite understanding of the absolute Being. ‘Consequently: the timeless being and existence is in no way contingent; and neither the philosopher nor the historian is able to give a theory of its origin: the factual existence in time appears as contingent because apparently it can be otherwise; however, this appearance originates from the | |
[pagina 483]
| |
fact that it is not comprehended: the philosopher can, to be sure, say in general that the One inconceivable, just like the infinite comprehending of the same, is such as it is, for the very reason that it is to continue being understood to infinity; he can, however, not at all deduce it genetically, and define it from this infinite comprehending, because then he would have conceived infinity, which is absolutely impossible. Here consequently is his limit, and, if he desires to know something in this department (realm), he is referred to experience. As little can the historian point out genetically this inconceivable (infinity) as the original beginning of time. His calling is to expose the factual successive determinations of empirical existence. Empirical existence itself and all the conditions of it are consequently presupposed by him’Ga naar voetnoot1. In this way Fichte comes to the conclusion that neither the philosopher nor the historian can say anything about the origin of the world or of mankind: ‘for there is no origin at all, but only the one timeless and necessary Being.’ The philosopher has only to account for the conditions of factual existence ‘as lying beyond all factual existence and all experience.’ What Fichte had in mind with this actually epistemological task of philosophy with respect to the science of history, appears clearly from his statement: ‘It acquires a definite concept of what is truly asked for by history and what belongs to it, besides a logic of historical truth; and so, even in this infinite territory, the groping about at random is replaced by the sure proceeding according to a rule’Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
[pagina 484]
| |
Fichte also mentions more precisely the relationship in which the components of historical development to be known apriori stand in his opinion to those to be known aposteriori. History is beyond doubt conceived of by Fichte as the development of culture which does not begin before the ‘Normalvolk’ postulated by him, was dispersed over the ‘seats of rudeness and barbarism.’ This ‘Normalvolk’ is supposed to have been in a situation of perfect ‘Vernunftkultur’ and such ‘through its mere existence, without any science or art.’ ‘Now for the first time something new and remarkable presented itself that stimulated the remembrance of men to retain it: - now for the first time could begin the true history which can do nothing more than notice factually, by means of mere experience, the gradual cultivation of the true human race of history, originated from a mixture of the original culture and the original barbarism’Ga naar voetnoot1. The metaphysically conceived apriori component of historical development is the formerly discussed world-plan that leads mankind through the five periods of world-history. Without any historical experience the philosopher can know that these periods must follow one another: ‘Now this development of the human race does not make its entrance in the general manner in which the philosopher paints it in one single survey, but gradually, disturbed by forces strange to it, at definite times, in definite places, under definite circumstances. All these particular surroundings do by no means originate from the Idea of this world-plan; they are the non-understood in it, and, as it is the only Idea for this world-plan, the non-understood in general; and here the pure empiricism of history makes its entrance, its a posteriori: the history proper in its form’Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
[pagina 485]
| |
The irrational, new element, not to be repeated, that can be discovered only empirically, fills the time-series of historical development and arises in the subjection of raw nature through rational and free cultural activity of the human race in the various forms of the absolute Idea. In this is seen the ‘transcendental-logical’ criterion of history in Fichte's first main work on the philosophy of history. | |
Fichte's new hstorical concept of time.Remarkable to a high degree and yet scarcely observed up to now is the fact that Fichte has paid special attention also to historical time. He distinguishes the true historical time from empty time. In the latter, there moves only dream and show, all that which serves only for pastime or for the mere satisfaction of a curiosity that is not grounded in a serious desire for knowledge: ‘The pastime is truly an empty time which is placed in the midst between the time filled up by serious business.’ In the ‘true and real time’, on the contrary, something happens, ‘when it becomes a principle, a necessary ground and cause of new phenomena which never before existed. Then for the first time a living life has arisen which originates other life from itself’Ga naar voetnoot1. We see here how Fichte in a typical manner anticipates the historical conception of time of the modern philosophy of life. Its distinction of true and apparent time is still to engage our attention in detail in our further discussion of this problem. Yet, in spite of everything that is offered in the ‘Grundzüge’ for the development of an irrationalist logic of the science of history, the fundamental dualism between the merely empirical | |
[pagina 486]
| |
individuality and the individuality of value in history is not yet bridged over here. Consequently, at this stage the historical logic exhibits a fundamental hiatus. Indeed, the true science of history remains restricted to the ‘Sammlung der blossen Facten’ (collection of mere facts), the professional historian remains one ‘who in collecting historical facts has no other criterion but the external sequence of the years and centuries ‘ohne alle Rücksicht auf ihren Inhalt’Ga naar voetnoot1 (without any regard to their content) even though his work is called ‘useful and honourable.’ Now Lask has demonstrated, that in the writings between 1805-9, this dualism between empirical individuality and value, not yet overcome in the ‘Grundzüge’, is removed in fact, by reason of the explicit ascription of value-character to that which is recognized as irrational with respect to its logical structure. Not until the last phase of all (namely in the Staatslehre of 1813) is the ascription of value-character to the historical material of experience (logically recognized as irrational) made a problem, which was possible only by means of a deepening of the methodological inquiries begun in 1805. Indeed we find for the first time in the important considerations on the Deduction of the ‘Gegenstand’ of the History of Mankind in the Staatslehre of 1813, properly speaking an elaboration of the task set in the Grundzüge: the discovery of the logic of historical truth. | |
In the ‘Staatslehre’ of 1813, Fichte anticipates the ‘cultural-historical’ method of the South-West German school of Neo-Kantianism. The synthesis of nature and freedom in the concept of the ‘free force’.Here for the first time a serious attempt is made to find a synthesis between nature and freedom within the transcendentally analysed historical field of inquiry. The manner in which Fichte tries to reach this synthesis is characteristic of the irrationalist motive which is operative behind the critical form. Fichte begins his views with setting a sharp antithesis between the ‘realm of nature’ (as the domain of the naturalistic science-ideal) and the ‘realm of freedom’ (as the domain of the ideal of personality). These two realms are now synthetically unified by an inter- | |
[pagina 487]
| |
mediate concept, i.e. that of the free force: ‘Nature is death and rest: freedom only must vivify and stimulate it again; according to a concept; and this is the very character of the free force, that it can only be moved according to a concept’Ga naar voetnoot1. ‘Consequently - and that is the point here - we acquire in that which is possibly given, besides that which is given in nature, also a world of freedom-products, constructed through absolute freedom on the basis of the former, however, not at all grounded on this nature which was closed with this dead force.’ ‘From this (originates) the sphere of the freedom-products, as being possibly given and under a particular condition: these (freedom-products) are contingent for the intuition, however qualified for the very history as a description of what in this way is given’ (italics mine)Ga naar voetnoot2. The following dilemma presents itself directly in Fichte's world-picture, which knows no modal law-spheres: The realm of ‘dead nature’ is ruled by the mathematical and mechanical laws imposed by the understanding; the realm of living actual freedom by the autonomous moral law. To which laws is now subjected the third realm, that of history as the synthetical realm of visible, cultural freedom? Fichte emphatically observes: ‘The ethical (realm) is purely spiritual and without figure, it is a law without any image. It acquires its concrete figure only from the ethical matter’Ga naar voetnoot3. Consequently, history in its individual figures and its ‘free forces’ which produce culture, must be characterized as ‘lawless’. To Fichte there is no other solution possible: ‘The state | |
[pagina 488]
| |
of affairs is therefore as follows: by far the greater part of the freedom-products present in a period of time of the intuition, have not come about according to the clear concept of the moral law, consequently not according to this law; no more have they come about by the law of nature, since the latter is closed to the creation of these products which have originated from freedom. Since there is no legislation besides these two, this (originating) occurs quite lawless, at random. This is truly, as is well known, the object of human history as it has developed until now...’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
The ‘hidden conformity to law’ of historical development. The irrationalist concept of the law.Thus the historical aspect is brought into explicit opposition to that which is conformed to a law: ‘a particular historical matter is to be understood only through history in general; the latter again is only to be understood through its opposite, that which happens in conformity to laws and is, consequently, to be known in a strictly scientific way’Ga naar voetnoot2. Nevertheless, to this statement, Fichte immediately adds the remark that the freedom which discloses itself in historical development must possess a hidden conformity to a law which is nothing other than the providence of the moral deity. But this conformity to a law is not to be known from rational concepts. It is rather a hidden telos in the displaying of the given freedom in the irrational development of culture which makes the transcendent values visible in the individual temporal formations of culture. Here, in a Humanistic perversion of the Christian faith in the Divine Providence, the law is very clearly made a simple | |
[pagina 489]
| |
reflection of the individual free subjectivity, disclosed in the ‘irrational process’Ga naar voetnoot1. The irrational historical conformity to law, which Fichte accepts, is the very negation of veritable historical norms. It is the precipitation of the irrationalist ideal of personality, in which the νόμος is nothing but the reflection of the individual αὐτόςGa naar voetnoot2. Only by conceiving the individual in its turn as a member of an individual community whose historical tradition and ‘common spirit’ is an inner constitutive factor of the individuality of all of its members, can this irrationalism escape the anarchistic view of history. Therefore, it must result in a universalist conception of temporal human society which - in polar opposition to individualism - views society according to the schema of the whole and its parts, not considering the inner nature of the different social relations. | |
Irrationalizing of the divine world-plan.The divine world-plan, that Fichte in his ‘Grundzüge’, still tried to deduce rationalistically in a purely apriori fashion, apart from the historical material of experience, is now, on the contrary, sought in the very individuality of the historical matter which cannot be comprehended in rational concepts: ‘However, is there not in this inconceivable incomprehensible element at | |
[pagina 490]
| |
the same time a world-plan, therefore undoubtedly a Providence and an Understanding? So what is the law of the world-facts, i.e. of that which gives to freedom its task? This question lies very deep; until now I have helped myself by ignoring and denying! I might there indeed arrive at a deeper, truly absolute Understanding, giving the inner support to the infinite modifiability of freedom. Therefore, that which I posited as absolutely factual, might perhaps yet be posited by an Understanding’Ga naar voetnoot1. It is clear, that in this final phase of Fichte's thought, the principium individuationis has shifted to the historical realm, as the synthesis of value and temporal reality, whereas, in his first rationalistic period, he had sought it - in accordance with Kant - only in the sensory matter of nature-experience. The apriori conformity to a law which the ‘Staatslehre’ assumes for historical development, i.e. the gradual conquest of faith by the understanding, is merely a formal one. It is only the qualitatively individual, moral nature, which, as given freedom, produces the material of history, since it becomes an individual paradigm for the producing by freedom. Its first appearance is a creative wonder of Providence, transformed by Fichte into a ‘transcendental-logical condition’ of the possibility of history: ‘Consequently: the concept of a moral procreation or nature of man has replaced Providence (as a Miracle), which is the ground of the truly historical material of history. According to our Idea we have immediately taken up this morality of nature into the necessary form of appearance’Ga naar voetnoot2. As the very ‘transcendental-logical’ condition for the possibility of an historical experience, the presence of a ‘moral | |
[pagina 491]
| |
nature’ may not be accepted further than is necessary for the explanation of the development. | |
The concept of the ‘highly gifted people’ (das geniale Volk).Fichte takes a further step in the development of his irrationalist methodology of history by transferring the concept of the miraculous from the individual to social groups or communities viewed as ‘individual totalities’. Just as an individual paradigm is postulated for the historical development of the morality of the individual, the social paradigm of an entire people is postulated for the moral development of the human race: ‘However, since we must conceive the appearance of freedom as a totality absolutely closed in time, we must assume some society which compels and instructs without itself having needed both, since, by its mere existence, it possessed this very morality to which it leads the society coming after it and originating from it, by means of compulsion and instruction: because it was by nature that to which others have to educate themselves in freedom under its cultivating power’Ga naar voetnoot1. In this way the hypothesis (introduced for the first time in the ‘Grundzüge’) as to a primeval people that is in possession of a morality, given in an individual moral nature, is now rendered serviceable to the methodology of history. By virtue of its very non-recurrent individual and ‘lawless’ realization of value, the historical development receives in Fichte a higher value-accent than that which recurs periodically according to the uniformity of natural laws. The historical is no longer, in a rationalistic fashion, set in opposition to the law of reason and in this opposition conceived of as the value-less (because law-less) material of experience; but it is rather understood as totality of what is new and creative individual in opposition to the merely ‘stehende Sein’ (static being) of natureGa naar voetnoot2. Fichte's conception, in sharp opposition to that of Kant, is | |
[pagina 492]
| |
now to the effect that the framing of ‘final ends’ of historical development, such as: ‘education for freedom’, ‘education for clarity’, etc. can have only the significance of a general descriptive formulation: ‘Both, however, are only formal. For the infinite content of this freedom, the moral task, remains in fact something incomprehensible, the image of God, for this very reason that the latter is absolutely incomprehensible, and is to be experienced only in the revelations of history’Ga naar voetnoot1. The concept of revelation in the sense of a synthesis of irrationality and originality is now expressly taken up in the ‘transcendental-logical’ structure of history. In this way the religious life in the historical-empirical form of Jesus is characterized as immediate individual revelation of the Idea of God in the appearanceGa naar voetnoot2. It will, consequently, have to be conceded to Lask, that in Fichte there has actually been developed a transcendental logic of history in contrast with the metaphysics of Hegel. The concept of science here developed finds, as we believe we have demonstrated in detail, its transcendental root in a cosmonomic Idea inspired by the irrationalist ideal of personality. | |
The inner antinomies in this irrationalist logic of history.If this conception is thought through consistently it must resolve itself into inner antinomies. For, on the one hand, by reason of its immanent continuity-postulate, it knows cosmic boundaries of meaning as little as the concept of science that originated from the naturalistic science-ideal; consequently it brings all normative subject-functions of temporal reality under a historical basic denominator. On the other hand, by its denaturing of historical conformity to law into a mere reflection of individual subjectivity, it must deny all knowable historical determination of facts. For de-termination can only issue from a law, which cannot be a mere reflection of individual subjectivity, but which regulates and limits the subject-functions in their infinite individual diversity. In our discussion of the | |
[pagina 493]
| |
modal structure of the historical aspect in the second volume we shall return to this point. | |
Law and individuality.Notwithstanding all its concreteness and individualization, a real law can never acquire the function of a mere register of the subjective facts in their complete individuality. The concept of a hidden, eternally incomprehensible conformity to law is contradictory and establishes in scientific thought only endless confusion, since it elevates to the status of law the temporal individual subjectivity itself which cannot really exist unless it is bound to a supra-individual order. Even the circumstance that Fichte does not view historical development as a uniform progress but rather as a process with hindrances and reactions, exhibits the impossibility of carrying through the irrationalist concept of history. For hindrances and reactions are to be recognized scientifically only under the test of a supra-subjective standard. The dangerous historistic tendency in Fichte's so-called ‘spiritual-scientific’ thought discloses itself in its pregnant sense at the same point at which it has won permanent gains for the science of history, namely, in the discovery of the national community of a people as an individual historical totality in contrast with the atomistic cosmopolitan view of the ‘Aufklärung’ (Enlightenment). Attention has been drawn sufficiently to the great gain of this discovery in modern Fichte-literature. In Kant's time, individualism was willing to acknowledge, beyond the atomistic individual conceived in natural-scientific terms, only the abstract universal concept of humanity in an ethical sense. Surely under the influence of Romanticism, which also is to be observed in Schleiermacher's principle of ‘Eigentümlichkeit’ (singularity), Fichte breaks radically with this individualistic point of view: ‘The form of a people itself is from nature or God: a certain highly individual manner to advance the aim of reason. Peoples are individualities with particular talents and character for it.’ ‘This then is a people in the higher sense of the word taken from the view-point of a spiritual world in general: the whole of men who continue living together in society and originate continuously themselves from themselves naturally and spiritually, a whole that is subject to some particular law of development of the divine from it. It is the common | |
[pagina 494]
| |
bond of this particular law that in the eternal world, and for that very reason also in the temporal, joins this multitude to a natural and self-conscious totality’Ga naar voetnoot1. | |
The ‘historical nationality’ as ‘true reality’ contrasted with the state as conceptual abstraction.Fichte now shows clearly his historistic view of society. He opposes the nationality - which he conceived as a purely historical entity - to the state. The former is, according to him, a full and true temporal reality, the state, on the contrary, a mere conceptual abstraction. He thereby paved the way for the most recent historistic-phenomenological theory of human society. The newly discovered historical aspect of reality is forthwith absolutized as the basic denominator for all aspects of human society and the national community of the people is elevated to the rank of ‘true historical reality’ which has an ‘earthly eternity’: ‘People and fatherland in this signification, as bearer and pledge of earthly eternity, and as that which down here can be eternal, lies far above the state in the ordinary sense of the word, - above the social order as it is conceived in a mere clear concept, and à propos of this concept is established and kept up’Ga naar voetnoot2. | |
[pagina 495]
| |
Insofar as Fichte here directs his polemic against the abstract individualistic conception of human society in the school of natural law he is again right to a certain extent. But his intention goes much further. Nationality is absolutized as the true historical revelation of the eternal spiritual community of humanity. The Humanistic ideal of personality here shows a most dangerous irrationalist and transpersonalist turn. Fichte's conception concerning the relation of nation and state is in principle the same as that of the ‘Historical School’. In the most recent times it has been elaborated in detail in the irrationalist and so-called ‘pluralistic’ sociology of Georges GurvitchGa naar voetnoot1. |
|